Citation for this page in APA citation style.           Close


Philosophers

Mortimer Adler
Rogers Albritton
Alexander of Aphrodisias
Samuel Alexander
William Alston
Anaximander
G.E.M.Anscombe
Anselm
Louise Antony
Thomas Aquinas
Aristotle
David Armstrong
Harald Atmanspacher
Robert Audi
Augustine
J.L.Austin
A.J.Ayer
Alexander Bain
Mark Balaguer
Jeffrey Barrett
William Barrett
William Belsham
Henri Bergson
George Berkeley
Isaiah Berlin
Richard J. Bernstein
Bernard Berofsky
Robert Bishop
Max Black
Susanne Bobzien
Emil du Bois-Reymond
Hilary Bok
Laurence BonJour
George Boole
Émile Boutroux
Daniel Boyd
F.H.Bradley
C.D.Broad
Michael Burke
Lawrence Cahoone
C.A.Campbell
Joseph Keim Campbell
Rudolf Carnap
Carneades
Nancy Cartwright
Gregg Caruso
Ernst Cassirer
David Chalmers
Roderick Chisholm
Chrysippus
Cicero
Randolph Clarke
Samuel Clarke
Anthony Collins
Antonella Corradini
Diodorus Cronus
Jonathan Dancy
Donald Davidson
Mario De Caro
Democritus
Daniel Dennett
Jacques Derrida
René Descartes
Richard Double
Fred Dretske
John Dupré
John Earman
Laura Waddell Ekstrom
Epictetus
Epicurus
Austin Farrer
Herbert Feigl
Arthur Fine
John Martin Fischer
Frederic Fitch
Owen Flanagan
Luciano Floridi
Philippa Foot
Alfred Fouilleé
Harry Frankfurt
Richard L. Franklin
Bas van Fraassen
Michael Frede
Gottlob Frege
Peter Geach
Edmund Gettier
Carl Ginet
Alvin Goldman
Gorgias
Nicholas St. John Green
H.Paul Grice
Ian Hacking
Ishtiyaque Haji
Stuart Hampshire
W.F.R.Hardie
Sam Harris
William Hasker
R.M.Hare
Georg W.F. Hegel
Martin Heidegger
Heraclitus
R.E.Hobart
Thomas Hobbes
David Hodgson
Shadsworth Hodgson
Baron d'Holbach
Ted Honderich
Pamela Huby
David Hume
Ferenc Huoranszki
Frank Jackson
William James
Lord Kames
Robert Kane
Immanuel Kant
Tomis Kapitan
Walter Kaufmann
Jaegwon Kim
William King
Hilary Kornblith
Christine Korsgaard
Saul Kripke
Thomas Kuhn
Andrea Lavazza
Christoph Lehner
Keith Lehrer
Gottfried Leibniz
Jules Lequyer
Leucippus
Michael Levin
Joseph Levine
George Henry Lewes
C.I.Lewis
David Lewis
Peter Lipton
C. Lloyd Morgan
John Locke
Michael Lockwood
Arthur O. Lovejoy
E. Jonathan Lowe
John R. Lucas
Lucretius
Alasdair MacIntyre
Ruth Barcan Marcus
Tim Maudlin
James Martineau
Nicholas Maxwell
Storrs McCall
Hugh McCann
Colin McGinn
Michael McKenna
Brian McLaughlin
John McTaggart
Paul E. Meehl
Uwe Meixner
Alfred Mele
Trenton Merricks
John Stuart Mill
Dickinson Miller
G.E.Moore
Thomas Nagel
Otto Neurath
Friedrich Nietzsche
John Norton
P.H.Nowell-Smith
Robert Nozick
William of Ockham
Timothy O'Connor
Parmenides
David F. Pears
Charles Sanders Peirce
Derk Pereboom
Steven Pinker
Plato
Karl Popper
Porphyry
Huw Price
H.A.Prichard
Protagoras
Hilary Putnam
Willard van Orman Quine
Frank Ramsey
Ayn Rand
Michael Rea
Thomas Reid
Charles Renouvier
Nicholas Rescher
C.W.Rietdijk
Richard Rorty
Josiah Royce
Bertrand Russell
Paul Russell
Gilbert Ryle
Jean-Paul Sartre
Kenneth Sayre
T.M.Scanlon
Moritz Schlick
Arthur Schopenhauer
John Searle
Wilfrid Sellars
Alan Sidelle
Ted Sider
Henry Sidgwick
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong
J.J.C.Smart
Saul Smilansky
Michael Smith
Baruch Spinoza
L. Susan Stebbing
Isabelle Stengers
George F. Stout
Galen Strawson
Peter Strawson
Eleonore Stump
Francisco Suárez
Richard Taylor
Kevin Timpe
Mark Twain
Peter Unger
Peter van Inwagen
Manuel Vargas
John Venn
Kadri Vihvelin
Voltaire
G.H. von Wright
David Foster Wallace
R. Jay Wallace
W.G.Ward
Ted Warfield
Roy Weatherford
C.F. von Weizsäcker
William Whewell
Alfred North Whitehead
David Widerker
David Wiggins
Bernard Williams
Timothy Williamson
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Susan Wolf

Scientists

David Albert
Michael Arbib
Walter Baade
Bernard Baars
Jeffrey Bada
Leslie Ballentine
Marcello Barbieri
Gregory Bateson
Horace Barlow
John S. Bell
Mara Beller
Charles Bennett
Ludwig von Bertalanffy
Susan Blackmore
Margaret Boden
David Bohm
Niels Bohr
Ludwig Boltzmann
Emile Borel
Max Born
Satyendra Nath Bose
Walther Bothe
Jean Bricmont
Hans Briegel
Leon Brillouin
Stephen Brush
Henry Thomas Buckle
S. H. Burbury
Melvin Calvin
Donald Campbell
Sadi Carnot
Anthony Cashmore
Eric Chaisson
Gregory Chaitin
Jean-Pierre Changeux
Rudolf Clausius
Arthur Holly Compton
John Conway
Jerry Coyne
John Cramer
Francis Crick
E. P. Culverwell
Antonio Damasio
Olivier Darrigol
Charles Darwin
Richard Dawkins
Terrence Deacon
Lüder Deecke
Richard Dedekind
Louis de Broglie
Stanislas Dehaene
Max Delbrück
Abraham de Moivre
Bernard d'Espagnat
Paul Dirac
Hans Driesch
John Eccles
Arthur Stanley Eddington
Gerald Edelman
Paul Ehrenfest
Manfred Eigen
Albert Einstein
George F. R. Ellis
Hugh Everett, III
Franz Exner
Richard Feynman
R. A. Fisher
David Foster
Joseph Fourier
Philipp Frank
Steven Frautschi
Edward Fredkin
Benjamin Gal-Or
Howard Gardner
Lila Gatlin
Michael Gazzaniga
Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen
GianCarlo Ghirardi
J. Willard Gibbs
James J. Gibson
Nicolas Gisin
Paul Glimcher
Thomas Gold
A. O. Gomes
Brian Goodwin
Joshua Greene
Dirk ter Haar
Jacques Hadamard
Mark Hadley
Patrick Haggard
J. B. S. Haldane
Stuart Hameroff
Augustin Hamon
Sam Harris
Ralph Hartley
Hyman Hartman
Jeff Hawkins
John-Dylan Haynes
Donald Hebb
Martin Heisenberg
Werner Heisenberg
John Herschel
Basil Hiley
Art Hobson
Jesper Hoffmeyer
Don Howard
John H. Jackson
William Stanley Jevons
Roman Jakobson
E. T. Jaynes
Pascual Jordan
Eric Kandel
Ruth E. Kastner
Stuart Kauffman
Martin J. Klein
William R. Klemm
Christof Koch
Simon Kochen
Hans Kornhuber
Stephen Kosslyn
Daniel Koshland
Ladislav Kovàč
Leopold Kronecker
Rolf Landauer
Alfred Landé
Pierre-Simon Laplace
Karl Lashley
David Layzer
Joseph LeDoux
Gerald Lettvin
Gilbert Lewis
Benjamin Libet
David Lindley
Seth Lloyd
Hendrik Lorentz
Werner Loewenstein
Josef Loschmidt
Ernst Mach
Donald MacKay
Henry Margenau
Owen Maroney
David Marr
Humberto Maturana
James Clerk Maxwell
Ernst Mayr
John McCarthy
Warren McCulloch
N. David Mermin
George Miller
Stanley Miller
Ulrich Mohrhoff
Jacques Monod
Vernon Mountcastle
Emmy Noether
Donald Norman
Alexander Oparin
Abraham Pais
Howard Pattee
Wolfgang Pauli
Massimo Pauri
Wilder Penfield
Roger Penrose
Steven Pinker
Colin Pittendrigh
Walter Pitts
Max Planck
Susan Pockett
Henri Poincaré
Daniel Pollen
Ilya Prigogine
Hans Primas
Zenon Pylyshyn
Henry Quastler
Adolphe Quételet
Pasco Rakic
Nicolas Rashevsky
Lord Rayleigh
Frederick Reif
Jürgen Renn
Giacomo Rizzolati
Emil Roduner
Juan Roederer
Jerome Rothstein
David Ruelle
David Rumelhart
Tilman Sauer
Ferdinand de Saussure
Jürgen Schmidhuber
Erwin Schrödinger
Aaron Schurger
Sebastian Seung
Thomas Sebeok
Franco Selleri
Claude Shannon
Charles Sherrington
David Shiang
Abner Shimony
Herbert Simon
Dean Keith Simonton
Edmund Sinnott
B. F. Skinner
Lee Smolin
Ray Solomonoff
Roger Sperry
John Stachel
Henry Stapp
Tom Stonier
Antoine Suarez
Leo Szilard
Max Tegmark
Teilhard de Chardin
Libb Thims
William Thomson (Kelvin)
Richard Tolman
Giulio Tononi
Peter Tse
Alan Turing
Francisco Varela
Vlatko Vedral
Mikhail Volkenstein
Heinz von Foerster
Richard von Mises
John von Neumann
Jakob von Uexküll
C. S. Unnikrishnan
C. H. Waddington
John B. Watson
Daniel Wegner
Steven Weinberg
Paul A. Weiss
Herman Weyl
John Wheeler
Wilhelm Wien
Norbert Wiener
Eugene Wigner
E. O. Wilson
Günther Witzany
Stephen Wolfram
H. Dieter Zeh
Semir Zeki
Ernst Zermelo
Wojciech Zurek
Konrad Zuse
Fritz Zwicky

Presentations

Biosemiotics
Free Will
Mental Causation
James Symposium
 
Thomas Sturm Thomas.Sturm@uab.cat via listserv.liv.ac.uk 4:12 AM (5 hours ago)

to PHILOS-L Dear all,

I received many answers to my query concerning discussions of claims about computers as discoverers. Many thanks to all who kindly sent me references and materials.

Before I list the references below, let me reflect on one point. I was looking specifically for criticisms and discussions made by cognitive scientists themselves, especially up to the early 1990s. There are some such criticisms, but not many (e.g. by Gorman in the special issue of Social Studies of Science 1989, or Johnson-Laird & Legrenzi in International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1992; see below). Instead, most came from philosophers and sociologists of science. That might be interpreted differently.

First, the cognitive science community might still widely have accepted the idea at that time. Perhaps because it was convinced of it, perhaps because it doesn't like to engage in fundamental disputes over its own research program. Second, as is well known, "cognitive science" is an ambiguous term, referring sometimes more narrowly to AI research and/or computer science insofar as it's concerned with cognition, but sometimes also to include (among other disciplines) philosophy. So, the philosophical criticisms coming from Dreyfus, Hempel, Gillies and others might be considered "internal" criticisms. Third, the discovery programs developed by Langley, Simon et al. were specifically directed against the idea that discovery isn't a rational (or logical) process. Because the latter was a philosophical thesis, the Langley-Simon-et-al. program was specifically discussed by philosophers of science (and then within science studies more generally - it aroused quite a number of worries among friends of the strong program in SSK). Fourth and finally, let's not underestimate the possibility that the following reference list may be biased due to what's available in the minds of this group - I did not ask a listgroup in cognitive science. (I will perhaps.)

I do not decide which interpretation is the best. I just did not want to deliver the digest without noting that the criticisms didn't come so much from practicing cognitive scientists, i.e. those writing and running the programs. - I include all references sent to me, including those after the early 1990s. People might be interested in the discussions no matter at which time they were brought forward.

Kind regards, Thomas

Alai, M. 2000. Informatica e logica della scoperta. In A. Andronico, G. Casadei, G. Sacerdoti (eds.), Didamatica 2000. Informatica per la didattica. Il Ponte Vecchio, Cesena, vol. 1, 13-19.

Alai, M. 2004. AI, scientific discovery and realism. Minds and Machines, 14, 21-42.

Collins, H. 1990. Artificial experts: Social knowledge and intelligent machines. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Dawson, Michael (various)

Dreyfus, H. 1972. What computers can't do. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (with a new introductory essay republished 1992 as: What Computers Still Can't Do.)

Fuller, S. 1989, rev. ed. 1993. Philosophy of science and its discontents. New York: Guilford Press. Esp.

Fuller, S. & Collier, J. 1993. Philosophy, rhetoric and the end of knowledge. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Esp. ch. 5.

Gillies, D. 1996. Artificial intelligence and scientific method. Oxford: OUP.

Heeffer, A. (forthcoming somewhere). Data-driven induction in scientific discovery. A critical assessment based on Kepler’s discoveries.

Hempel, C.G. 1987. Thoughts on the limitations on discovery by computers. In Schaffner, K. (ed.), Logic of discovery and diagnosis in medicine (pp. 115-122). Berkeley: UC Press.

Gardner, H. 1985. The mind's new science. New York: Basic Books

Korb, K. B. & C. Wallace. 1997. In search of the philosopher's stone: remarks on Humphreys and Freedman's critique of causal discovery. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 543--553

Pearl. 2009. Causality. (a positive "proof" of the program, on causal Bayesian networks)

Pylyshyn, Z. 1984. Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Radder, H. 2011. The world observed/the world conceived. Pittsburg: U of Pittsburgh Press. Esp. ch 12. Here: http://digital.library.pitt.edu/cgi-bin/t/text/text-idx?c=pittpress;cc=pittpress;view=toc;idno=31735062136373

Spirtes, R., Glymour, C. & Scheines, R. 1993. Causation, Prediction, and Search. Springer. (2nd ed. MIT 2001) (a positive "proof" of the program, on causal Bayesian networks)

Tweney, R. 1990. 5 questions for computationalists. In J. Shrager & P. Langley (eds.), Computational models of scientific discovery and theory formation (pp. 471-484). Palo Alto, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

Tweney, R. 1992. Serial and parallel distributed processing in scientific discovery. In R. Giere (ed.), Cognitive models of science (Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of science, XV, pp. 77-88). Minneapolis: U of Minnesota Press.

Weber, M. 2005. Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge: CUP. Esp. ch. 3

Weisberg, R.M. 2006. Creativity: Understanding innovation in problem solving, science, invention, and the arts. Wiley.

Special issues of:

- Social Studies of Science 1989, 4. (Lead article by P. Slezak, Scientific discovery as empirical refutation of the strong programme. Comments and replies by Brannigan, Collins, Fuller, Thagard, Woolgar, Myers, Slezak, Simon, Giere, Gorman, and Slezak.

- International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume 6, Issue 1, 1992. (Lead article by H. Simon, Scientific discovery as problem solving. Comments and replies by Agassi, Cordeschi, De May, Gillies, Hesse, Johnson-Laird & Legrenzi, Losee, Marconi, Newton-Smith, Petroni, Schank & Hughes, Trautteur, Watkins, and Simon)

More positive "proof" that was offered:

Science 3 April 2009: Vol. 324 no. 5923 pp. 81-85, DOI: 10.1126/science.1165893, "Distilling Free-Form Natural Laws from Experimental Data"

Science 3 April 2009: Vol. 324 no. 5923 pp. 85-89 DOI: 10.1126/science.1165620, "The Automation of Science"

Science 9 January 2004: Vol. 303 no. 5655 pp. 186-195 DOI: 10.1126/science.1088172 "How Enzymes Work: Analysis by Modern Rate Theory and Computer Simulations"

----- Missatge original ----- De: Thomas Sturm Data: Dimarts, Febrer 25, 2014 6:50 pm Assumpte: Query: Criticisms of Scientific Discovery by Computer?

> Dear all,

> I'm looking for good critical discussions of the claim made by > Herbert Simon (et al.) that scientific discoveries can be carried > out, or simulated, by computers. I'm particularly (but not > exclusively) interested in criticisms made by cognitive scientists > or psychologists before or around the 1990s.

> Any suggestions? Please reply off-list. I'm happy to produce a > digest at the end should people want one.

> Kind regards, Thomas Sturm >

Dr. Thomas Sturm
Departament de Filosofia
Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona
Edifici B
E-08193 Bellaterra (Barcelona)
España/Spain
Phone: +34 935 86 8173 - Fax: +34 935 81 2001

Normal | Teacher | Scholar