Citation for this page in APA citation style.           Close


Philosophers

Mortimer Adler
Rogers Albritton
Alexander of Aphrodisias
Samuel Alexander
William Alston
Anaximander
G.E.M.Anscombe
Anselm
Louise Antony
Thomas Aquinas
Aristotle
David Armstrong
Harald Atmanspacher
Robert Audi
Augustine
J.L.Austin
A.J.Ayer
Alexander Bain
Mark Balaguer
Jeffrey Barrett
William Barrett
William Belsham
Henri Bergson
George Berkeley
Isaiah Berlin
Richard J. Bernstein
Bernard Berofsky
Robert Bishop
Max Black
Susanne Bobzien
Emil du Bois-Reymond
Hilary Bok
Laurence BonJour
George Boole
Émile Boutroux
Daniel Boyd
F.H.Bradley
C.D.Broad
Michael Burke
Lawrence Cahoone
C.A.Campbell
Joseph Keim Campbell
Rudolf Carnap
Carneades
Nancy Cartwright
Gregg Caruso
Ernst Cassirer
David Chalmers
Roderick Chisholm
Chrysippus
Cicero
Randolph Clarke
Samuel Clarke
Anthony Collins
Antonella Corradini
Diodorus Cronus
Jonathan Dancy
Donald Davidson
Mario De Caro
Democritus
Daniel Dennett
Jacques Derrida
René Descartes
Richard Double
Fred Dretske
John Dupré
John Earman
Laura Waddell Ekstrom
Epictetus
Epicurus
Austin Farrer
Herbert Feigl
Arthur Fine
John Martin Fischer
Frederic Fitch
Owen Flanagan
Luciano Floridi
Philippa Foot
Alfred Fouilleé
Harry Frankfurt
Richard L. Franklin
Bas van Fraassen
Michael Frede
Gottlob Frege
Peter Geach
Edmund Gettier
Carl Ginet
Alvin Goldman
Gorgias
Nicholas St. John Green
H.Paul Grice
Ian Hacking
Ishtiyaque Haji
Stuart Hampshire
W.F.R.Hardie
Sam Harris
William Hasker
R.M.Hare
Georg W.F. Hegel
Martin Heidegger
Heraclitus
R.E.Hobart
Thomas Hobbes
David Hodgson
Shadsworth Hodgson
Baron d'Holbach
Ted Honderich
Pamela Huby
David Hume
Ferenc Huoranszki
Frank Jackson
William James
Lord Kames
Robert Kane
Immanuel Kant
Tomis Kapitan
Walter Kaufmann
Jaegwon Kim
William King
Hilary Kornblith
Christine Korsgaard
Saul Kripke
Thomas Kuhn
Andrea Lavazza
Christoph Lehner
Keith Lehrer
Gottfried Leibniz
Jules Lequyer
Leucippus
Michael Levin
Joseph Levine
George Henry Lewes
C.I.Lewis
David Lewis
Peter Lipton
C. Lloyd Morgan
John Locke
Michael Lockwood
Arthur O. Lovejoy
E. Jonathan Lowe
John R. Lucas
Lucretius
Alasdair MacIntyre
Ruth Barcan Marcus
Tim Maudlin
James Martineau
Nicholas Maxwell
Storrs McCall
Hugh McCann
Colin McGinn
Michael McKenna
Brian McLaughlin
John McTaggart
Paul E. Meehl
Uwe Meixner
Alfred Mele
Trenton Merricks
John Stuart Mill
Dickinson Miller
G.E.Moore
Thomas Nagel
Otto Neurath
Friedrich Nietzsche
John Norton
P.H.Nowell-Smith
Robert Nozick
William of Ockham
Timothy O'Connor
Parmenides
David F. Pears
Charles Sanders Peirce
Derk Pereboom
Steven Pinker
Plato
Karl Popper
Porphyry
Huw Price
H.A.Prichard
Protagoras
Hilary Putnam
Willard van Orman Quine
Frank Ramsey
Ayn Rand
Michael Rea
Thomas Reid
Charles Renouvier
Nicholas Rescher
C.W.Rietdijk
Richard Rorty
Josiah Royce
Bertrand Russell
Paul Russell
Gilbert Ryle
Jean-Paul Sartre
Kenneth Sayre
T.M.Scanlon
Moritz Schlick
Arthur Schopenhauer
John Searle
Wilfrid Sellars
Alan Sidelle
Ted Sider
Henry Sidgwick
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong
J.J.C.Smart
Saul Smilansky
Michael Smith
Baruch Spinoza
L. Susan Stebbing
Isabelle Stengers
George F. Stout
Galen Strawson
Peter Strawson
Eleonore Stump
Francisco Suárez
Richard Taylor
Kevin Timpe
Mark Twain
Peter Unger
Peter van Inwagen
Manuel Vargas
John Venn
Kadri Vihvelin
Voltaire
G.H. von Wright
David Foster Wallace
R. Jay Wallace
W.G.Ward
Ted Warfield
Roy Weatherford
C.F. von Weizsäcker
William Whewell
Alfred North Whitehead
David Widerker
David Wiggins
Bernard Williams
Timothy Williamson
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Susan Wolf

Scientists

David Albert
Michael Arbib
Walter Baade
Bernard Baars
Jeffrey Bada
Leslie Ballentine
Marcello Barbieri
Gregory Bateson
Horace Barlow
John S. Bell
Mara Beller
Charles Bennett
Ludwig von Bertalanffy
Susan Blackmore
Margaret Boden
David Bohm
Niels Bohr
Ludwig Boltzmann
Emile Borel
Max Born
Satyendra Nath Bose
Walther Bothe
Jean Bricmont
Hans Briegel
Leon Brillouin
Stephen Brush
Henry Thomas Buckle
S. H. Burbury
Melvin Calvin
Donald Campbell
Sadi Carnot
Anthony Cashmore
Eric Chaisson
Gregory Chaitin
Jean-Pierre Changeux
Rudolf Clausius
Arthur Holly Compton
John Conway
Jerry Coyne
John Cramer
Francis Crick
E. P. Culverwell
Antonio Damasio
Olivier Darrigol
Charles Darwin
Richard Dawkins
Terrence Deacon
Lüder Deecke
Richard Dedekind
Louis de Broglie
Stanislas Dehaene
Max Delbrück
Abraham de Moivre
Bernard d'Espagnat
Paul Dirac
Hans Driesch
John Eccles
Arthur Stanley Eddington
Gerald Edelman
Paul Ehrenfest
Manfred Eigen
Albert Einstein
George F. R. Ellis
Hugh Everett, III
Franz Exner
Richard Feynman
R. A. Fisher
David Foster
Joseph Fourier
Philipp Frank
Steven Frautschi
Edward Fredkin
Benjamin Gal-Or
Howard Gardner
Lila Gatlin
Michael Gazzaniga
Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen
GianCarlo Ghirardi
J. Willard Gibbs
James J. Gibson
Nicolas Gisin
Paul Glimcher
Thomas Gold
A. O. Gomes
Brian Goodwin
Joshua Greene
Dirk ter Haar
Jacques Hadamard
Mark Hadley
Patrick Haggard
J. B. S. Haldane
Stuart Hameroff
Augustin Hamon
Sam Harris
Ralph Hartley
Hyman Hartman
Jeff Hawkins
John-Dylan Haynes
Donald Hebb
Martin Heisenberg
Werner Heisenberg
John Herschel
Basil Hiley
Art Hobson
Jesper Hoffmeyer
Don Howard
John H. Jackson
William Stanley Jevons
Roman Jakobson
E. T. Jaynes
Pascual Jordan
Eric Kandel
Ruth E. Kastner
Stuart Kauffman
Martin J. Klein
William R. Klemm
Christof Koch
Simon Kochen
Hans Kornhuber
Stephen Kosslyn
Daniel Koshland
Ladislav Kovàč
Leopold Kronecker
Rolf Landauer
Alfred Landé
Pierre-Simon Laplace
Karl Lashley
David Layzer
Joseph LeDoux
Gerald Lettvin
Gilbert Lewis
Benjamin Libet
David Lindley
Seth Lloyd
Hendrik Lorentz
Werner Loewenstein
Josef Loschmidt
Ernst Mach
Donald MacKay
Henry Margenau
Owen Maroney
David Marr
Humberto Maturana
James Clerk Maxwell
Ernst Mayr
John McCarthy
Warren McCulloch
N. David Mermin
George Miller
Stanley Miller
Ulrich Mohrhoff
Jacques Monod
Vernon Mountcastle
Emmy Noether
Donald Norman
Alexander Oparin
Abraham Pais
Howard Pattee
Wolfgang Pauli
Massimo Pauri
Wilder Penfield
Roger Penrose
Steven Pinker
Colin Pittendrigh
Walter Pitts
Max Planck
Susan Pockett
Henri Poincaré
Daniel Pollen
Ilya Prigogine
Hans Primas
Zenon Pylyshyn
Henry Quastler
Adolphe Quételet
Pasco Rakic
Nicolas Rashevsky
Lord Rayleigh
Frederick Reif
Jürgen Renn
Giacomo Rizzolati
Emil Roduner
Juan Roederer
Jerome Rothstein
David Ruelle
David Rumelhart
Tilman Sauer
Ferdinand de Saussure
Jürgen Schmidhuber
Erwin Schrödinger
Aaron Schurger
Sebastian Seung
Thomas Sebeok
Franco Selleri
Claude Shannon
Charles Sherrington
David Shiang
Abner Shimony
Herbert Simon
Dean Keith Simonton
Edmund Sinnott
B. F. Skinner
Lee Smolin
Ray Solomonoff
Roger Sperry
John Stachel
Henry Stapp
Tom Stonier
Antoine Suarez
Leo Szilard
Max Tegmark
Teilhard de Chardin
Libb Thims
William Thomson (Kelvin)
Richard Tolman
Giulio Tononi
Peter Tse
Alan Turing
Francisco Varela
Vlatko Vedral
Mikhail Volkenstein
Heinz von Foerster
Richard von Mises
John von Neumann
Jakob von Uexküll
C. S. Unnikrishnan
C. H. Waddington
John B. Watson
Daniel Wegner
Steven Weinberg
Paul A. Weiss
Herman Weyl
John Wheeler
Wilhelm Wien
Norbert Wiener
Eugene Wigner
E. O. Wilson
Günther Witzany
Stephen Wolfram
H. Dieter Zeh
Semir Zeki
Ernst Zermelo
Wojciech Zurek
Konrad Zuse
Fritz Zwicky

Presentations

Biosemiotics
Free Will
Mental Causation
James Symposium
 
David Widerker

David Widerker independently developed a criticism of Harry Frankfurt's attacks on his Principle of Alternate Possibilities (PAP) that was similar to but stronger than Robert Kane's criticism in the 1970's.

Frankfurt's Principle of Alternate Possibilities states that:

(PAP) A person is morally responsible for what he has done only if she could have done otherwise, that is, only if she could have avoided performing it.

Frankfurt's attack depends on a very clever demon or intervener who has the power to block certain of the agent's alternative possibilities, while allowing the agent to act on that one of the possibilities that the demon wants to occur. Frankfurt then argues that if the agent chooses on her own that possibility, then the readiness of the intervener to prevent other possibilities is irrelevant to her decision.

(IRR) There may be circumstances that in no way bring it about that a person performs a certain action; nevertheless, those very circumstances make it impossible for him to avoid performing that action.

In order to know whether to block the action of an agent, Kane and Widerker pointed out that there would need to exist a prior sign that the action was now going to occur. Such a necessary and sufficient prior sign would exist only in a deterministic and strictly causal universe.

Since Frankfurt's intervening demon, much like Laplace's demon, has no way of knowing the actual information about future events - such as an agent's decisions - until that information comes into existence, such demons are not possible and Frankfurt-style thought experiments, entertaining as they are, can not in fact establish the compatibilist version of free will.

Other philosophers, notably Alfred Mele and David Robb, Derk Pereboom, and others have developed more clever attacks on PAP. Widerker and others have developed further defenses, and there have been a number of such rounds.

In his latest paper in the Journal of Philosophy (v 103, no 4, April 2006 , p.163), Widerker has said that he too can imagine conceptually possible situations where the agent’s decision is not causally determined, yet it is not within the agent’s power to refrain from it.

The avoidability-independent account of moral blame to which I have been calling attention here places me in the camp of those called "Source Incompatibilists" who hold that, although moral responsibility is incompatible with determinism, moral responsibility does not require that the agent could have avoided acting as he did. On this view, moral responsibility just requires that the agent was the ultimate originator of his act, that is, he performed the act without being in any way caused or nomically determined to perform it. Perhaps a better term for such a position would be “Frankfurt-friendly libertarianism.”
Note that the discussion is less about whether the agent has libertarian free will than it is focused on moral responsibility. Widerker says:
I do acknowledge the intuitive force of Frankfurt’s claim that the agent in an IRR-situation is blameworthy for what he did, even though that he could not have done otherwise. But here, too, my way of accounting for this intuition differs from Frankfurt’s. Frankfurt sees the reason for the falsity of PAP in the fact that the unavoidability of the agent’s act (the factor that renders it unavoidable) did not play any role in the causal explanation of the act. I, on the other, hand, attribute the failure of PAP to the fact that the agent, in acting as he did in an IRR-situation, showed a lack of respect for morality (that is, chose on his own to act contrary to the requirements of morality without being morally justified in doing so), and to the observation that this negative verdict would still apply even if one were to assume that the agent’s act was avoidable. However, the difficulties I find with Frankfurt’s position in no way detract from the importance of Frankfurt’s achievement, that is, that by drawing our attention to the possibility of IRR-scenarios and their moral implications, Frankfurt has profoundly deepened our understanding of the notions of freedom and responsibility.
For Teachers
For Scholars
Excerpts from Blameworthiness and Frankfurt's Argument Against the Principle of Alternative Possibilities
From Moral Responsibility and Alternative Possibilities, ed. David Widerker and Michael McKenna, 2006, p.53-54
1. Introduction

A widely accepted moral principle affirms that

PAP: An agent is morally responsible for performing a given act A only if he could have avoided performing it.
In his seminal article 'Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility,' Harry Frankfurt (1969) has attacked this principle. Central to his argument is the following assumption:
IRR: There may be circumstances in which a person performs some action which, although they make it impossible for him to avoid performing that action, they in no way bring it about that he performs it. (Frankfurt, 1969, pp. 830, 837)
Frankfurt contends that in a situation of the sort described in IRR (call it an `IRR-situation') the agent is morally responsible for what he did even though he could not have avoided so acting. Hence, according to him, PAP is false. To establish IRR, Frankfurt appeals to an example of the following sort:
Jones is deliberating whether or not to keep a certain promise he made to his uncle. Unbeknownst to Jones, there is another person, Black, who for some reason does not want Jones to keep his promise. Black has the power and the means to force Jones to break the promise. But wishing to avoid showing his hand unnecessarily, he has made up his mind to intervene if and only if Jones does not show a sign of going to decide to break the promise. Call that sign 'S1'. If Jones does show that sign, then Black does nothing, knowing that in this case Jones will act as he (Black) wants him to act. (it is assumed that Black knows Jones very well in this regard.) Finally, suppose that Jones decides to break the promise for reasons of his own.
It seems that in this situation Jones acts freely without Black's intervention, and therefore is morally responsible for what does. But, given Black's presence, it would appear that he cannot avoid deciding to break the promise. Call this example 'Promise Breaking.'

In Widerker (1995a), I argued, adopting a libertarian position with regard to freedom and moral responsibility, that examples such as Promise-Breaking fail to establish IRR and that, therefore, Frankfurt's argument against PAP does not succeeds Most importantly, I tried to show that his argument fails when applied to simple mental acts such as deciding, choosing, undertaking, forming an intention, that is, acts which for the libertarian constitute the loci of moral responsibility. Essentially, my argument was this: either the sign S1, which Black employs as a sign for not intervening, is (or is indicative of) something that, in the circumstances, is causally sufficient for Jones's decision at t to break his promise or it is not. If it is, then the example does not describe an IRR-situation, since the latter requires that the decision must not be causally determined. On the other hand, if S1 is not so associated with Jones's decision to break the promise, if S1 is merely a reliable indicator of it, then there is no reason to think that Jones's decision was unavoidable. In either case, the truth of IRR has not been established.

In this chapter, I wish to advance the debate over the strength of Frankfurt's attack on PAP in two ways. First, I shall consider some new attempts to provide examples of IRR-situations and contend that they do not succeed either. Second, and more important, granting (for the sake of discussion) Frankfurt's assumption that IRR-situations are possible, I shall provide a comprehensive defense of PAP for one sense of 'morally responsible,' that of moral blameworthiness.

An agent is morally blameworthy for performing a given act A only if he could have avoided performing it.
(Henceforth, whenever I refer to PAP, I shall be referring to this construal of it.) I shall develop my defense of PAP (i) by questioning the moral assumptions employed by Frankfurt in his argument against PAP; (ii) by articulating and defending the basic intuition behind PAP; and (iii) by indicating how a defender of PAP might go about explaining away the intuition many share that in an IRR-situation in which the agent performed a morally wrong act, he is morally blameworthy for what he did.
4. A Defense of PAP (the W-defense) (p.63-64)

Can the defender of PAP go further? Can he also show that there are good reasons to accept PAP, reasons that would explain why in an IRR-situation the agent should not be deemed morally blameworthy for the act he performed? This question is important, since although many will agree that Frankfurt's argument against PAP is unconvincing, they may still think that IRR-situations provide intuitive counterexamples to PAP. They may emphasize the fact that in situations of this sort the agent acts freely, doing what he does for reasons of his own without being coerced or causally determined to so act. They may, therefore, rightly wonder why (in the absence of any excusing factor) the proponent of PAP still thinks that such an agent should be exonerated. Can the PAP-defender allay this worry? I believe he can. To show this, let us focus on a specific example of an IRR-situation, say, some (suitably revised) version of the Promise-Breaking example mentioned earlier. Now consider the following reply by the defender of PAP.

Let me grant, for the sake of discussion, that in the IRR-situation under consideration, Jones acted freely in the sense that what he did he did for reasons of his own without being causally determined or coerced to so act. Still, since you, Frankfurt, wish to hold him blameworthy for his decision to break his promise, tell me what, in your opinion, should he have done instead? Now, you cannot claim that he should not have decided to break the promise, since this was something that was not in Jones's power to do. Hence, I do not see how you can hold Jones blameworthy for his decision to break the promise.
Call this defense the 'What-should-he-have-done defense' or for short the 'W-defense'. The W-defense points to an important reason why it would be unreasonable to regard an agent morally blameworthy in an IRR-situation. When we consider someone morally blameworthy for a certain act, we do so because we believe that morally speaking he should not have done what he did. This belief is essential to our moral disapproval of his behavior. Sometimes, however, such a belief may be unreasonable, for example, in a situation in which it is clear to us that the agent could not have avoided acting as he did. To expect in that situation that the agent should not have done what he did is to expect him to have done the impossible. By implication, considering him blameworthy because he has not fulfilled this unreasonable expectation would be unreasonable.

The W-defense thus suggests the following general constraint on ascriptions of moral blame: PAE: An agent S is morally blameworthy for doing A only if under the circumstances it would be morally reasonable to expect S not to have done A.

This principle, which may be called 'the principle of alternative expectations' (PAE), enables the PAP-defender to formulate an intuitive argument for PAP.

(1) An agent S is morally blameworthy for doing A only if under the circumstances it would be morally reasonable to expect S not to have done A.

(2) If S could not have avoided doing A, then on pain of expecting him to have done the impossible, it would be morally unreasonable to expect him not to have done A.

(3) Hence, if S could not have avoided doing A, then S is not morally blameworthy for doing A.28

Note that PAE is a more general principle than PAP, since it can be used to explain why we sometimes exonerate an agent in situations in which his wrongful behavior was avoidable. These, for example, may be situations in which that behavior resulted from his being unaware of the causal consequences of some act of his, or where it can be traced to insufficient moral knowledge on his part. In each of these cases, there is no reason to assume that the agent could not have avoided acting wrongly. Finally, note that PAE can be further generalized so as to yield a full necessary and sufficient condition for ascriptions of moral blame.
A person is morally blameworthy for doing A iff in doing A he acted in a morally wrong way, and under the circumstances it was morally reasonable to expect him not to have done A.
8. Conclusion (p.69)

There is a widely held view among moral philosophers that Frankfurt's attack on PAP constitutes a definitive refutation of the traditional libertarian conception of freedom and moral responsibility. Elsewhere, I have argued against this conclusion by questioning the coherence of the type of scenario on which Frankfurt bases his attack (Widerker, 1995a, 1995b). In this chapter, I have tried to advance the debate over the plausibility of PAP further (i) by considering and rejecting more sophisticated counterexamples to PAP, and (ii) by casting doubt upon the moral assumptions underlying Frankfurt's attack. Furthermore, I have tried to articulate the basic intuition underlying PAP, and have also indicated how the defender of this principle might go about explaining away the intuition many share that, provided Frankfurt-type scenarios are coherent, the agent in those scenarios is blameworthy for what he does. What I hope to have shown is that the dispute between Frankfurt and PAP-defenders is not merely a dispute over the question whether such scenarios are possible, but is a more fundamental dispute that rests on conflicting intuitions about our notion of moral blame.

An Exchange between Widerker and Fischer
John Martin Fischer proposed that Frankfurt-style counter-examples to the principle of alternate possibilities could be used to refute "avoidability," the traditional libertarian condition on freedom and moral responsibilty that the agent was not causally determined and could have avoided the decision.

Widerker showed that Fischer's attack on libertarianism failed, using a variation of the Kane-Widerker Objection to Frankfurt examples generally.


Chapter 1.4 - The Philosophy Chapter 1.6 - The Scientists
Home Part Two - Knowledge
Normal | Teacher | Scholar