Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Dupré John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker U.T.Place Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars David Shiang Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong Peter Slezak J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing C. S. Unnikrishnan Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium |
Bernard Berofsky
Bernard Berofsky is a well-known champion of determinism. He edited the influential anthology Free Will and Determinism in 1966, including some very important papers, such as "Free Will as Involving Determination and Inconceivable Without It" by R. E. Hobart, "Free Will as Involving Determinism" by Phillipa Foot, and "Freedom and Responsiblity" by P. H. Nowell-Smith.
These papers helped to establish determinism (or compatibilism) as the dominant view of philosophers in the late twentieth century, at least until Peter van Inwagen's 1982 Essay on Free Will restated the standard arguments against free will as his "Consequence Argument" and "Mind Argument, and Robert Kane's 1985 Free Will and Values claimed quantum indeterminism could provide human freedom without jeopardizing control."
In the introduction to Free Will and Determinism, Berofsky laments the lack of a good definition of determinism in most works on human freedom.
In discussions of human freedom it is not uncommon to omit a definition or clarification of the thesis of determinism, although reference to it may be made. This is quite serious if one considers (1) the fact that this thesis often plays a fundamental role in conceptions of human freedom and (2) the possibility that resolutions of fundamental questions about human freedom hinge upon clarification of the thesis of determinism.Berofsky spends over five pages in his introduction on religious determinism, questions like divine foreknowledge, but only one page on science. And in the science section there is no mention of quantum indeterminism. In 1971 Berofsky published his book Determinism, in which he gave an abstract and formal definition of determinism in mathematical, logical, and analytical philosophical terms: (x) [x is an R-sentence ⊃ (∃y) (∃z) (y is a state description-sentence • z is a law-sentence • (y • z) ⊃ x)] An R-sentence is true, contingent, singular, and temporal. It must not contain a causal, evaluative, or basic dispositional predicate. Any logical consequence of either an R-sentence or any conjunction of R-sentences is an R-sentence. If the predicate of the R-sentence is a determinable whose determinates admit as values any or almost any real number, the laws in the deterministic account of this sentence must contain variables for that determinable that may also take values from any or almost any real number (Continuity-requirement). A state description-sentence is a conjunction of any mathematical, logical, and linguistic truths, any true sentences of the form "x = y," and the state description proper. The state description proper is a subset of R-sentences except that sentences containing basic dispositional predicates are allowed, and sentences containing positional and temporal predicates are ruled out. The state description must be logically and criterially independent of the sentence the deterministic account is about; and no sentence may refer to a time period subsequent to t where t is the temporal designation in the sentence the deterministic account is about. No other temporal restrictions on state descriptions are made. A law (as used in the definition of determinism) is a true, logically contingent universal conditional with non-self-contradictory, open-ended, nonpositional, and qualitative predicates that meets five requirements (DS, C, S, AE, D). ("A law" may actually be a conjunction of laws.) A deterministic account of some R-sentence is, of course, a specific state description-sentence and a specific law (or laws) that entails the R-sentence. Thus, any deterministic account of x is a deterministic account of each logical consequence of x. Moreover, a deterministic account of an R-sentence may be povided by several deterministic accounts of sentences which conjunctively entail that R-sentence.Berofsky maintains three things (Determinism, pp.1-3):
No philosophical problem is more deserving of the title 'the free will problem' than that concerning the assessment of the claim that a deterministic world, i.e., one governed completely by universal scientific law, has no room for agents with dignity sufficient to justify attributions of moral responsibility to them.Berofsky notes that the "incompatibilist" assumes that moral responsibility presupposes that the world is not deterministic. He extends the definition of incompatibilist, amazed that others have not also done this: We shall also extend the term "incompatibilist" in a perfectly natural way to one who applies his reasoning to a particular case by concluding that an agent is not morally responsible for an action in the event that that particular action is determined. It is a psychological mystery to me why so few writers on this subject note the significance of this extension. Although it is virtually a truism that an incompatibilist draws an important conclusion about some determined action regardless of the truth or falsity of the general thesis of determinism, many philosophers regard the free will problem as having been deprived of its motivation once determinism is surrendered. This response is as viable as a refusal to see the danger in an arsenic-laced apple because not all the apples in the basket are laced with arsenic.We agree that a single determined action does not 1) imply that all actions are determined, or 2) imply that the action is predetermined back to the beginning of the universe by a causal chain, as pointed out so clearly by Phillipa Foot in her important article anthologized by Berofsky in 1966. In Berofsky's last book, Liberation from Self in 1995, he turns to psychology to explore the notion of human autonomy. Defying the etymological origins1, he denies that autonomous agents are individuals whose actions are self directed. He says I will argue that autonomy is essentially constituted by the manner in which an agent is engaged in her world rather than the metaphysical origin of her motivations. (p.1) Critics of the view that freedom is the liberty of indifference are fond of observing that our freedom is not threatened by the need to subordinate ourselves to the rules of mathematics and logic. We do not feel that we would have greater freedom (at least of a worthwhile sort) if we retained the ability to withhold judgment in the face of deductively conclusive evidence. I believe that we should feel similarly unafraid by the correlative need to subordinate ourselves to the other areas of life in which we act and find our satisfactions. In this way, autonomy is achieved. (p.2) ...there is something perverse in wanting the freedom to reject a theorem one knows to be true. (p.2) Autonomous persons must be independent, not just from the pernicious influence of others, but from the pernicious influence of their own earlier lives. For that robust engagement with the world is possible only for persons who have liberated themselves from the disabling effects of physiological and psychological afflictions. We are all limited and, perhaps, our lives are completely determined. But there are crucial differences in the manner in which our earlier life bears on our later life. The possibly deterministic process that has brought us to our current state may have an independence and authenticity depending on the character of current interactions. The autonomy of a sculptor is grounded in knowledge of the craft, its techniques, its history, its standards, in his openness, and in his ability to respond to relevant inputs, his work as it has so far evolved, his own responses to that work, and relevant features of the world such as the manner of his involvement in professional life. If these elements are in place, we do not require in addition a radical rupture with the past. On the other hand, when we have formed and retained an irrational belief that is rendered immune from learning through experience, when we respond to the world in a cognitive style that is prone to produce distortion, when our experience is filtered through subjective principles designed to reinforce prejudices which serve a defensive function, we have failed to transcend our origins in a way that bears on our capacity to establish an autonomous connection to the world. In order to characterize impediments to autonomy, therefore, we must turn to psychology for a deeper understanding of the ways these barriers can form. It is striking to observe that this is done by very few philosophers who are interested in autonomy. (p.2-3)In 2003, Berofsky contributed an article on "Classical Compatibilism" to Moral Responsibility and Alternative Possibilities, edited by Michael McKenna and David Widerker. He describes a "Strong Compatibilism" that rules out alternative possibilities and claims that "Classical Compatibilism" does not rule them out: Those philosophers who draw depressing consequences about human freedom and responsibility from the existence of deterministic accounts' usually do so because they draw an intermediate conclusion that has been characterized in a variety of ways: from the fact that a particular action is determined, the conclusion is drawn that the agent could not have done otherwise (or that the action is necessitated or that there is no alternative possibility or that the action is inevitable, and so on). Some compatibilists believe that freedom does not require determinism and, therefore, concede to the incompatibilist the possibility of a freedom-assuring indeterministic process of deliberation leading to a decision D at t1. Some of these compatibilists believe as well that such a process can exist alongside a distinct mechanism that insures but does not determine that D occur at t1. The presence of the distinct insuring mechanism guarantees that the agent could not have done otherwise, while the agent's freedom over the decision is ostensibly assured by the fact that it is the result, not of the distinct mechanism, but rather of the deliberative process. The latter incorporates whatever elements are deemed essential for freedom, one of which the libertarian believes is indetermination. The incompatibilist's complaint that determinism rules out freedom and moral responsibility by ruling out an agent's ability to do otherwise is thereby rendered otiose — determinism is harmless even if it entails that everything we do we must do. Call this strategy 'strong compatibilism,' a label whose qualifier designates immunity from refutation by the 'discovery' that deterministic accounts entail that an agent could not have done otherwise. Strong compatibilists do not believe that all freedom-assuring deliberative processes are indeterministic. They are compatibilists, after all, and believe that the key freedom-conferring elements — deciding not under coercion or compulsion for reasons one is neither constrained nor compelled to possess — may be found in some deterministic processes as well. In this respect, of course, they part ways with the libertarian. Their position is stronger than classical compatibilism, for the latter accepts the incompatibilist demand for alternative possibilities, but supposes that the demand fails to be met only when specific sorts of determining conditions are present. Classical compatibilists agree then with incompatibilists that the presence of a distinct process that renders the agent unable to choose otherwise negates the agent's prima facie freedom conferred by the deliberative process. They both see the agent as the victim of an illusion. For he deliberates in the belief that he faces open possibilities. It is also of some interest that, in the eyes of the classical compatibilist, since determination per se neither destroys freedom nor renders an agent unable to do otherwise, the destructive elements of the process that insures the decision must be different from simple determination.In recent journal articles, Berofsky has challenged the idea of "source incompatibilism", whether Robert Kane’s event-causal libertarianism or the various agent-causal varieties defended by Derk Pereboom and Randolph Clarke. He says We are very different from machines and the lower animals. We are complex creatures who often deliberate about a multiplicity of options. We reflect and make decisions, often rationally, that we do not have to make. We occasionally have original ideas and create original products. We are to some extent responsible for the lives we lead, including the decisions we make...Even if we find ourselves with inculcated values, we can sometimes alter them upon reflection and adopt a new set of values.Berofsky says that there are very few philosophers who hold the extreme position that the discovery that this is a deterministic world would require us to abandon this picture entirely and to replace it with a picture of ourselves as puppets, devoid of any sort of freedom or dignity." But we could cite hard determinists who call themselves "illusionists" like Saul Smilansky and the psychologist Daniel Wegner. |