Laurence BonJour
(1943-)
Laurence BonJour criticizes much of contemporary epistemology. In his book
Epistemic Justification, he says that the typical concerns of recent epistemologists - the
Gettier problem, doubts about closure, the lottery paradox, contextual views, etc. - are "devouring much time and effort and philosophical cleverness and giving almost nothing back in return" (
A Companion to Epistemology, 2nd ed., p.118)
In a recent profile of his work, he says:
My epistemological thinking has focused primarily on a set of related issues that I take to
be the central issues of epistemology, both
historically and substantively. Do we have
good reasons for thinking that our various
beliefs about the world (primarily about
the common-sense world of material objects,
including its history and scientific nature)
are true? If we have such reasons, what is their
detailed nature and structure, and how ultimately cogent are they?
In recent epistemology, issues in this
vicinity have been standardly formulated in
terms of the concepts of knowledge and epistemic
justification; and my own discussion has often
been couched in these terms. I have lately
come to think, however, for reasons that are
briefly suggested in the final section of this self-
profile, that such formulations, are inessential and, to a significant degree, misleading.
What the great historical epistemologists
(here I have especially Descartes and Locke
in mind) were asking more than anything
else was, I believe, just the questions I have
mentioned, even though they often couched
them in terms of knowledge (though rarely, if
ever, in terms of the somewhat technical
notion of justification).
Much recent epistemological discussion
has been devoted to the issue between internalist and externalist theories of justification and knowledge. Here I shall only say
that, as I understand the issues listed above,
externalist views are simply irrelevant to
them: externalism may offer conceptions
of knowledge or of justification or perhaps
even (in what I can understand only as a
stipulated sense) of a reason for a belief, but
having a reason is an essentially internalist
notion.
(A Companion to Epistemology, 2nd ed., p.114)
One might think that BonJour's concern with "the common-sense world of material objects" would make him
externalist and leaning toward "
naturalizing" epistemology by using scientific methods. But BonJour is a strong
internalist who originally defended
coherentism but now defends "Pure Reason."
BonJour now argues for a Cartesian
foundationalism and
a priori justification. He describes his rationalist conception of the
a priori:
In contrast to the radical changes in my
views concerning empirical reasons, my position on a priori reasons has remained essentially unchanged. In opposition to the radical
empiricism that denies the very existence of a
priori reasons and the moderate empiricism
that insists that they are confined to claims
that are analytic, I have defended the traditional rationalist view that a priori insight
yields genuinely cogent reasons for accepting
non-analytic claims about the world.
My main argument for such a view is
extremely simple, but also, I believe, quite
compelling. It begins with two premises that
only a very extreme skeptic can deny: first,
that experience or observation provides, in
some way, direct reasons for accepting certain
empirical claims; and, second, that the class
of broadly empirical claims for which we
have good reasons is much larger than thai
for which there are reasons of this directly
experiential sort. (The former class would
include at least claims about unobserved
situations in the past and present, claims
about the future, claims about unobservable
entities of various sorts, and claims about
laws of nature.) The argument is then that
we can have a good reason for some claim in
this former class only if we have a logically
prior good reason for a conditional proposition
having some claim (or conjunction of claims)
supported by directly experiential reasons
as the antecedent and the claim in question
as the consequent. And the reason for this
conditional proposition can only be a priori,
since it is obviously not a matter of direct
experience.
(A Companion to Epistemology, 2nd ed., p.116)
BonJour accepts the traditional view that
a priori reasons are based on an immediate insight into the truth, indeed a
necessary truth.
Turning to the positive aspect of the concept
of an a priori reason, the traditional view,
which I believe to be essentially correct, is
that in the most basic cases such reasons
result from direct or immediate insight into
the truth, indeed the necessary truth, of the
relevant claim. A derivative class of a priori
reasons results from similar insights into
the derivability of a claim from one or more
premises for which such a priori reasons exist
or from a chain of such derivations. And a
partially a priori reason may result from an a
priori insight into the derivability of a claim
from others established on broadly empirical
grounds.
Here it is important to be clear that
insights of this sort are not supposed to be
merely brute convictions of truth, on a par with
hunches that may be psychologically compelling. On the contrary, a priori insights
purport to reveal not just that the claim in question must be true but also, at some level, why
this is so. They are thus putative insights into
the essential nature of things or situations
of the relevant kind, into the way that reality
in the respect in question must be. But, contrary to the most standard historical views,
the idea of an a priori reason does not imply
either: (i) that experience could not also
count for or against the claim in question; or
(ii) that an a priori reason could not be overridden by experience; or still less (iii) that an
a priori reason renders the claim certain or
infallible.
(A Companion to Epistemology, 2nd ed., p.117)
For Teachers
To hide this material, click on the Normal link.
For Scholars
To hide this material, click on the Teacher or Normal link.
Notes
1.
2.
Bibliography
Normal |
Teacher |
Scholar