Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Jeremy Butterfield Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza James Ladyman Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Ernest Nagel Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker U.T.Place Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars David Shiang Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong Peter Slezak J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Xenophon Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Simon Conway-Morris Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Dupré John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Augustin-Jean Fresnel Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg Grete Hermann John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Travis Norsen Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Frank Rosenblatt Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing C. S. Unnikrishnan Nico van Kampen Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington James D. Watson John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium |
Robert Hilary Kane Correspondence
Some Thoughts on Free Will
May 10, 2008
Dear Professor Kane,
I am an astrophysicist and cosmologist by training and have long been studying the way information (actually structure in general) is created and maintained in the universe. I earned my Ph.D. at Harvard in 1968 with a thesis on the quantum mechanics of the hydrogen molecule. The fundamental process of information creation, whether an atom forming from sub-atomic particles, a molecule - including DNA and biological structures, or a bit being set to one or zero in a computer, involves a quantum mechanical event in which a "measurement" is made that allows any "observer" to see the new structural element. Measurement is accompanied by radiating away an amount of entropy (or disorder) that more than compensates for the increase in order (negative entropy or information) that the structure represents in the universe. There are remarkable parallels in this process to what I would like to suggest to you is the "intelligible" model for free will you have sought for many years - I believe it extends your notion of Relativistic Alternatives and R-choice of Free Will and Values. Measurement begins with a thoroughly unpredictable microscopic quantum process, followed by a macroscopic process for which indeterminism is negligible. The core assumption in quantum mechanics is that the microscopic world is unpredictable, but the measurement apparatus can be treated classically because it is macroscopic. In my study of many philosophers and scientists who have pondered the question of free will, I find three thinkers who have discussed such a two-stage model for a free will - free, in the sense of random alternative possibilities, and will, in the sense of an adequately deterministic choice from the alternatives based on values in one's character (your UR if the choice has already become a fixed belief or habit, as Charles Peirce would say). They are William James (1897), Henri Poincaré (1906), and Karl Popper (1960). Daniel Dennett's "Valerian" model in Brainstorms (1868), which he eventually rejects, is derived from Poincaré, as reported by Jacques Hadamard, who quoted Valery. He also read Popper, but may have rejected Popper's mind/body dualism. I am beginning to put my thoughts onto some web pages, and would greatly appreciate your critical comments before approaching your philosophical colleagues, including Dennett, who is nearby (I am still in Cambridge). Perhaps we might have a chance to chat after the academic year ends and you have a bit of time? At your convenience, please take a look at my draft History of Free Will here: http://www. Please correct any wrong impression I may give about your own work there - and here. http://www. I am available to talk anytime at 617-876-5678, and would be happy to call you if you prefer. Cheers. Bob Re: Some Thoughts on Free Will
May 23, 2008
Dear Bob,I've read your history and found it quite interesting and well done. I'd quibble with a few historical points here and there, but would agree with most of it and find it's presentation of the history of the problem congenial to my way of looking at it. Some of the stuff, including the role of certain figures to the debate (e.g. Quetelet) were new to me. I also think that the two-stage approach is an important part of the solution to the problem of incompatibilist free will (and indicated as much in Free Will and Values, the Significance of Free Will and other works). But I think it must be supplemented by other moves to get the full picture. I in fact formulated a "Valerian" version of my own in the 70s about the same time as Dennett's, but never published it, because in my view it needed to be supplemented, which I did in subsequent works. Nonetheless it is an important key, as you suggest. I would enjoy talking sometime by phone. Unfortunately, it is a very difficult time for me right now, since my wife has been seriously ill and I am absorbed with family matters and other things. If things clear up as the summer unfolds, I will let you know by email and set something up. Best wishes, Robert Kane University Distinguished Teaching Professor Department of Philosophy The University of Texas at Austin 1 University Station C3500 Austin TX 78712 Office Phone: 512 471 6776 Department Phone: 512 471 4857 Department Fax: 512 471 4806 Re: Some Thoughts on Free Will
May 30, 2008
Dear Professor Kane,
Thanks for your encouraging words.
I look forward to a conversation with you sometime this summer when your wife is well again and you can find the time.
Cheers.
Bob
Re: Some Thoughts on Free Will
July 26, 2008
Hello Professor Kane,Thanks very much for your response. I do hope the summer finds your wife better and family matters working out well for you. I write now to tell you I just read your remarks in response to Fischer, Pereboom, and Vargas and am delighted with your following lines: ______________ "As it happens, on my libertarian account of free will, one does not need large-scale indeterminism in the brain, in the form, say, of macro-level wave function collapses (in the manner of the Penrose/Hameroff view mentioned by Vargas). Minute indeterminacies in the timings of firings of indeterminism neurons would suffice, because the indeterminism in my view plays only an interfering role, in the form of background noise. Indeterminism does not have to "do the deed" on its own, so to speak. One does not need a downpour of indeterminism in the brain, or a thunderclap, to get free will. Just a sprinkle will do." (Four Views on Free Will, p.183) ______________ You are quite right. Quantum (and even some thermal) noise is all we need to supply random unpredictable alternative possibilities. http://www. The only reasonable model for the indeterministic contribution is ever-present noise. We call it Micro Mind. (subconscious id) And indeterminism is NOT involved in the de-liberating will. We call it Macro Mind. (Critical superego apparatus) The major difference is how the two process noise in the brain circuits. Our "adequately determined" mind can overcome the noise whenever it needs to make a determination on thought or action. ______________ We distinguish six increasingly sophisticated ideas about the role of chance and indeterminism in the question of free will. Many libertarians have accepted the first two. Determinist and compatibilist critics of free will make the third their central attack on chance, claiming that it denies moral responsibility. But very few thinkers appear to have considered all six essential requirements for chance to contribute to libertarian free will.
In our Cogito model, "Free Will" combines two distinct concepts. Free
is the chance and randomness of the Micro Mind. Will is the adequate
determinism of the Macro Mind. And these occur in a temporal sequence.
Compatibilists and Determinists were right about the Will,
First comes the consideration of alternative possibilities,
which are generated unpredictably by acausal events (simply noise in
neural network communications). This free creation of possible thoughts
and actions allow one to feel "I can do otherwise."
Next comes de-liberation
and determination by the will, the unfreeing of possibilities into
actuality, the decision that directs the tongue or body to speak or
act.
After the deliberation of the will, the true sentence "I can do otherwise" can be changed to the past tense and remain true as a "hard fact" in the "fixed past," and written "I could have done otherwise."
Thus we have the temporal sequence which William James saw so clearly a century ago, with chance in a present time
of ambiguous random alternatives, leading to a choice which grants consent to one
possibility and transforms an equivocal future into an unalterable and simple past.
Free undetermined alternatives are followed by willed, determined choices.John Locke long ago thought it was inappropriate to describe the Will itself as Free. The Will is a Determination. It is the Man who is Free. "I think the question is not proper, whether the will be free, but whether a man be free," he wrote. "This way of talking, nevertheless, has prevailed, and, as I guess, produced great confusion." Cheers, Bob P.S., I am still expanding the history of free will and writing up major contributors to the history with their own pages on the website. http://www. Re: Some Thoughts on Free Will
August 3, 2008
BobI'm pleased you liked the quote from Four Views. I agree with about 90-95% of the subsequent commentary, but am unable to discuss any of it further at present and have had to cut back on many commitments because of health problems I am currently experiencing. Best wishes, Bob |