Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Dupré John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker U.T.Place Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars David Shiang Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong Peter Slezak J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing C. S. Unnikrishnan Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium |
The Quantum Postulate and the
Recent Development of Atomic Theory [Note: The text below is an annotated HTML version of the PDF version of the Nature paper. It is easily searched and allows cross references (hyperlinks) to other Bohr works defining "complementarity" that led to the "standard" and "orthodox" version of quantum physics called the Copenhagen Interpretation starting with an article by Werner Heisenberg in the 1950's. The "Quantum Postulate" refers in part to Bohr's "old quantum theory." Bohr postulated a discontinuous "quantum jump" of an electron between "stationary states" with the emission or absorption of radiation of frequency ν, in accordance with Planck's postulate E = hν and his "quantum of action" h. But note that for Bohr the radiation emitted or absorbed is continuous. He never endorsed Einstein's light-quantum hypothesis, although the Bohr atom is taught today as emitting a photon when the electron jumps between energy levels.]
The Quantum Postulate and the Recent Development of Atomic Theory.1
By Prof. N. BOHR, For. Mem. R.S.
IN connexion with the discussion of the physical
interpretation of the quantum theoretical
methods developed during recent years, I should
like to make the following general remarks regarding
the principles underlying the description of
atomic phenomena, which I hope may help to
harmonise the different views, apparently so divergent,
concerning this subject.
1. QUANTUM POSTULATE AND CAUSALITY. The quantum theory is characterised by the acknowledgment of a fundamental limitation in the classical physical ideas when applied to atomic phenomena. The situation thus created is of a peculiar nature, since our interpretation of the experimental material rests essentially upon the classical concepts.
The "quantum postulate" is Bohr's assumption of "stationary states" and the discontinuous "quantum jump" of an electron between states, with the emission of radiation of frequency ν, following Planck's 1900 postulate of discrete oscillators with energy E = hν, with h Planck's famous constant for the "quantum of action" .
Notwithstanding the difficulties
which hence are involved in the formulation
of the quantum theory, it seems, as we shall see,
that its essence may be expressed in the so-called
quantum postulate, which attributes to any atomic
process an essential discontinuity, or rather individuality,
completely foreign to the classical
theories and symbolised by Planck's quantum of
action.
This postulate implies a renunciation as regards
the causal space-time co-ordination of atomic processes.
Indeed, our usual description of physical
phenomena is based entirely on the idea that the
phenomena concerned may be observed without
disturbing them appreciably. This appears, for
example, clearly in the theory of relativity, which
has been so fruitful for the elucidation of the
classical theories. As emphasised by Einstein,
every observation or measurement ultimately rests
on the coincidence of two independent events at
the same space-time point. Just these coincidences
will not be affected by any differences which
the space-time co-ordination of different observers
otherwise may exhibit.
Bohr denied an "independent reality" to quantum phenomena; observation involves subjective elements dependent on both human senses and theoretical concepts.
The "point" at which the observation involves the quantum is called the Heisenberg "cut". Bohr later regretted his 'irrationality' comment.
Now the quantum postulate
implies that any observation of atomic
phenomena will involve an interaction with the
agency of observation not to be neglected.
Accordingly,
an independent reality in the ordinary
physical sense can neither be ascribed to the
phenomena nor to the agencies of observation.
After all, the concept of observation is in so far
arbitrary as it depends upon which objects are
included in the system to be observed. Ultimately
every observation can of course be reduced to our
sense perceptions. The circumstance, however,
that in interpreting observations use has always
to be made of theoretical notions, entails that for
every particular case it is a question of convenience
at what point the concept of observation involving
the quantum postulate with its inherent
'irrationality' is brought in.
If definition of a system state requires
This situation has far-reaching consequences.
On one hand, the definition of the state of
a physical system, as ordinarily understood,
claims the elimination of all external disturbances.
But in that case, according to the quantum
postulate, any observation will be impossible,
and, above all, the concepts of space and time
lose their immediate sense. On the other hand,
if in order to make observation possible we permit
certain interactions with suitable agencies
of measurement, not belonging to the system,
an unambiguous definition of the state of the
system is naturally no longer possible, and
there can be no question of causality in the
ordinary sense of the word.
no disturbance, then observation is impossible. If an observation interacts with the system, how are we to define causality? Space-time
co-ordination and the claim of causality are complementary.
They "symbolize" observation
The very nature of the
quantum theory thus forces us to regard the space-time
co-ordination and the claim of causality, the
union of which characterises the classical theories,
as complementary but exclusive features of the
description, symbolising the idealisation of observation
and definition respectively. Just as the relativity
theory has taught us that the convenience
of distinguishing sharply between space and time
rests solely on the smallness of the velocities
ordinarily met with compared to the velocity of
light, we learn from the quantum theory that the
appropriateness of our usual causal space-time
description depends entirely upon the small value
of the quantum of action as compared to the
actions involved in ordinary sense perceptions.
Indeed, in the description of atomic phenomena,
the quantum postulate presents us with
the task of developing a 'complementarity' theory
the consistency of which can be judged only by
weighing the possibilities of definition and observation.
and definition, also complementary? Relativity has a limit v / c → 0. Quantum mechanics has the limit h → 0 (better h / m → 0). The quantum mechanics of particles (1925) and the competing "wave mechanics" (1926) had just been developed. Bohr saw these as complementary, the waves in space-time, the particles needing causal interactions
This view is already clearly brought out by the
much-discussed question of the nature of light and
the ultimate constituents of matter. As regards
light, its propagation in space and time is adequately
expressed by the electromagnetic theory.
Especially the interference phenomena in vacuo
and the optical properties of material media are
completely governed by the wave theory superposition
principle. Nevertheless, the conservation
of energy and momentum during the interaction between radiation and matter, as evident in the photoelectric and Compton effect, finds its adequate expression just in the light quantum idea put forward by Einstein. The Bohr-Kramers-Slater denial of energy and momentum conservation (1924) had failed, and Einstein's "light-quantum hypothesis" just been confirmed by the Bothe-Geiger experiments.
As is well known, the
doubts regarding the validity of the superposition
principle on one hand and of the conservation laws
on the other, which were suggested by this apparent
contradiction, have been definitely disproved
through direct experiments. This situation would
seem clearly to indicate the impossibility of a
causal space-time description of the light phenomena.
On one hand, in attempting to trace
the laws of the time-spatial propagation of light
according to the quantum postulate, we are confined
to statistical considerations. On the other hand,
the fulfilment of the claim of causality for the
individual light processes, characterised by the
quantum of action, entails a renunciation as regards
the space-time description.
Once again, space-time and causality are complementary views of classical concepts.
Of course, there can
be no question of a quite independent application
of the ideas of space and time and of causality.
The two views of the nature of light are rather to
be considered as different attempts at an interpretation
of experimental evidence in which the
limitation of the classical concepts is expressed in
complementary ways.
The "wave-particle duality" first seen by Einstein in 1909 for light was applied to matter by Louis de Broglie in 1923, following Einstein's ideas.
The problem of the nature of the constituents of
matter presents us with an analogous situation.
The individuality of the elementary electrical
corpuscles is forced upon us by general evidence.
Nevertheless, recent experience, above all the
discovery of the selective reflection of electrons
from metal crystals, requires the use of the
wave theory superposition principle in accordance
with the original ideas of L. de Broglie. Just
as in the case of light, we have consequently in
the question of the nature of matter, so far as we
adhere to classical concepts, to face an inevitable
dilemma, which has to be regarded as the very
expression of experimental evidence.
Waves of radiation in free space and individual material particles are
In fact, here
again we are not dealing with contradictory but with
complementary pictures of the phenomena, which
only together offer a natural generalisation of the
classical mode of description. In the discussion
of these questions, it must be kept in mind that,
according to the view taken above, radiation
in free space as well as isolated material particles
are abstractions, their properties on the
quantum theory being definable and observable
only through their interaction with other systems.
Nevertheless, these abstractions are, as we shall
see, indispensable for a description of experience
in connexion with our ordinary space-time
view.
The difficulties with which a causal space-time
description is confronted in the quantum theory,
and which have been the subject of repeated
discussions, are now placed into the foreground by
the recent development of the symbolic methods.
complementary ideal abstractions. Isolation is impossible. Property definitions and their observations require interactions.
The "symbolic methods" are Heisenberg-Born-Jordan "quantum mechanics."
An important contribution to the problem of a
consistent application of these methods has been
made lately by Heisenberg (Zeitschr. f. Phys.,
43, 172; 1927). In particular, he has stressed the
peculiar reciprocal uncertainty which affects all
measurements of atomic quantities. Before we
enter upon his results it will be advantageous to
show how the complementary nature of the description
appearing in this uncertainty is unavoidable
already in an analysis of the most elementary
concepts employed in interpreting experience.
2. QUANTUM OF ACTION AND KINEMATICS.
The fundamental contrast between the quantum
of action and the classical concepts is immediately
apparent from the simple formulas which form the
common foundation of the theory of light quanta
and of the wave theory of material particles. If
Planck's constant be denoted by h, as is well known,
The "uncertainty" principle may only be epistemological limits on complementary observations?
E τ = I λ = h, . . . (1)
where E and I are energy and momentum respectively,
τ and λ the corresponding period of
vibration and wave-length. In these formulae the
two notions of light and also of matter enter in
sharp contrast. While energy and momentum are
associated with the concept of particles, and hence
may be characterised according to the classical
point of view by definite space-time co-ordinates,
the period of vibration and wave-length refer to a
plane harmonic wave train of unlimited extent in
space and time. Only with the aid of the superposition
principle does it become possible to attain
a connexion with the ordinary mode of description.
Indeed, a limitation of the extent of the wave-fields
in space and time can always be regarded as
resulting from the interference of a group of elementary
harmonic waves. As shown by de Broglie
(Thèse, Paris, 1924), the translational velocity of
the individuals associated with the waves can be
represented by just the so-called group-velocity.
Let us denote a plane elementary wave by
A cos 2π ( νt - xσx - yσy - zσz + δ ),
where A and δ are constants determining respectively
the amplitude and the phase. The quantity
ν = 1/τ is the frequency, σx, σy, σz the wave numbers
in the direction of the co-ordinate axes, which may
be regarded as vector components of the wave
number σ = l / λ. in the direction of propagation.
While the wave or phase velocity is given by ν / σ,
the group - velocity is defined by dν / dσ. Now
according to the relativity theory we have for a
particle with the velocity v :
I = ( v / c2 ) E and vdI = dE,
where c denotes the velocity of light. Hence by
equation (1) the phase velocity is c2 / v and the group-velocity
v. The circumstance that the former is
in general greater than the velocity of light emphasises
the symbolic character of these considerations.
At the same time, the possibility of identifying
the velocity of the particle with the group-velocity
indicates the field of application of space-time
pictures in the quantum theory.
The use of a wave description reduces sharpness in definitions
Here the complementary
character of the description appears,
since the use of wave-groups is necessarily accompanied
by a lack of sharpness in the definition of
period and wave-length, and hence also in the definition
of the corresponding energy and momentum
as given by relation (1).
Δt Δν = Δx Δσx = Δy Δσy = Δz Δσz = 1,
where Δt, Δx, Δy, Δz denote the extension of the
wave-field in time and in the directions of space
corresponding to the co-ordinate axes. These
relations — well known from the theory of optical
instruments, especially from Rayleigh's investigation
of the resolving power of spectral apparatus
— express the condition that the wave-trains
extinguish each other by interference at the
space-time boundary of the wave-field. They
may be regarded also as signifying that the group
as a whole has no phase in the same sense as the
elementary waves. From equation (1) we find
thus:
Δt ΔE = Δx ΔIx = Δy ΔIy = Δz ΔIz = h, . . (2)
as determining the highest possible accuracy in
the definition of the energy and momentum of the
individuals associated with the wave-field. In
general, the conditions for attributing an energy
and a momentum value to a wave-field by means
of formula (1) are much less favourable. Even
if the composition of the wave-group corresponds
in the beginning to the relations (2), it will in the
course of time be subject to such changes that it
becomes less and less suitable for representing an
individual. It is this very circumstance which
gives rise to the paradoxical character of the
problem of the nature of light and of material
particles. The limitation in the classical concepts
expressed through relation (2) is, besides, closely
connected with the limited validity of classical
mechanics, which in the wave theory of matter
corresponds to the geometrical optics, in which
the propagation of waves is depicted through
'rays.' Only in this limit can energy and momentum
be unambiguously defined on the basis
of space-time pictures. For a general definition
of these concepts we are confined to the conservation
laws, the rational formulation of which has
been a fundamental problem for the symbolical
methods to be mentioned below.
In the language of the relativity theory, the
content of the relations (2) may be summarised in
the statement that according to the quantum
theory a general reciprocal relation exists between
the maximum sharpness of definition of the space-time
and energy-momentum vectors associated
with the individuals.
Bohr may still hope to "reconcile" conservation laws by claiming space-time points are "unsharp" (reminiscent of his BKS statistical conservation ideas).
This circumstance may be
regarded as a simple symbolical expression for the
complementary nature of the space-time description
and the claims of causality. At the same time,
however, the general character of this relation
makes it possible to a certain extent to reconcile
the conservation laws with the space-time coordination
of observations, the idea of a coincidence
of well-defined events in a space-time point being
replaced by that of unsharply defined individuals
within finite space-time regions.
This circumstance permits us to avoid the
well-known paradoxes which are encountered in
attempting to describe the scattering of radiation
by free electrical particles as well as the
collision of two such particles.
Bohr-Kramers-Slater failed to combine instantaneous and discontinuous electron jumps with continuous radiation. Here Bohr hopes the electron can be spread out in a finite space-time region just as the radiation is?
According to
the classical concepts, the description of the
scattering requires a finite extent of the radiation
in space and time, while in the change
of the motion of the electron demanded by the
quantum postulate one seemingly is dealing with
an instantaneous effect taking place at a definite
point in space. Just as in the ease of radiation,
however, it is impossible to define momentum and
energy for an electron without considering a finite
space-time region. Furthermore, an application
of the conservation laws to the process implies
that the accuracy of definition of the energy
momentum vector is the same for the radiation
and the electron. In consequence, according to
relation (2), the associated space-time regions can
be given the same size for both individuals in
interaction.
A similar remark applies to the collision between
two material particles, although the significance of
the quantum postulate for this phenomenon was
disregarded before the necessity of the wave concept
was realised. Here this postulate does indeed
represent the idea of the individuality of the
particles which, transcending the space-time description,
meets the claim of causality. While the
physical content of the light quantum idea is
wholly connected with the conservation theorems for
energy and momentum, in the case of the electrical
particles the electric charge has to be taken into
account in this connexion. It is scarcely necessary
to mention that for a more detailed description
of the interaction between individuals we cannot
restrict ourselves to the facts expressed by formulae
(1) and (2), but must resort to a procedure
which allows us to take into account the coupling
of the individuals, characterising the interaction
in question, where just the importance of the
electric charge appears. As we shall see, such a
procedure necessitates a further departure from
visualisation in the usual sense.
3. MEASUREMENTS IN THE QUANTUM THEORY.
Heisenberg was upset that Bohr so strongly adopted Schrödinger's wave-mechanical views. Although wave mechanics and matrix mechanics were equivalent formulations of quantum mechanics, Bohr was emphasizing the wave-like properties, and embarrassing Heisenberg by pointing out the mistaken "disturbance" explanation of uncertainty in Heisenberg's γ-ray microscope.
In his investigations already mentioned on the
consistency of the quantum theoretical methods,
Heisenberg has given the relation (2) as an expression
for the maximum precision with which
the space-time co-ordinates and momentum-energy
components of a particle can be measured
simultaneously. His view was based on the
following consideration: On one hand, the coordinates
of a particle can be measured with any
desired degree of accuracy by using, for example,
an optical instrument, provided radiation of
sufficiently short wave-length is used for illumination.
According to the quantum theory, however,
the scattering of radiation from the object is always
connected with a finite change in momentum,
which is the larger the smaller the wave-length of
the radiation used. The momentum of a particle,
on the other hand, can be determined with any
desired degree of accuracy by measuring, for
example, the Doppler effect of the scattered radiation,
provided the wave-length of the radiation
is so large that the effect of recoil can be neglected,
but then the determination of the space co-ordinates
of the particle becomes correspondingly less
accurate.
The essence of this consideration is the inevitability
of the quantum postulate in the estimation
of the possibilities of measurement. A closer
investigation of the possibilities of definition would
still seem necessary in order to bring out the general
complementary character of the description. Indeed,
a discontinuous change of energy and momentum
during observation could not prevent us
from ascribing accurate values to the space-time
co-ordinates, as well as to the momentum-energy
components before and after the process. The
reciprocal uncertainty which always affects the
values of these quantities is, as will be clear from
the preceding analysis, essentially an outcome of
the limited accuracy with which changes in energy
and momentum can be defined, when the wave-fields
used for the determination of the space-time
co-ordinates of the particle are sufficiently small.
Ironically, Max Born (My Life, p.213) says that Heisenberg could not answer Wien's question on resolving power and nearly failed the oral exam for his doctorate.
Heisenberg looked up the answers to all the questions he could not answer, and the optical formula for resolution became the basis for his most famous work just a few years later.
But not before Bohr pointed out a mistake in Heisenberg's first draft suggesting that a "disturbance" was the source of the uncertainty. Heisenberg says he was "brought to tears."
In using an optical instrument for determinations
of position, it is necessary to remember that
the formation of the image always requires a
convergent beam of light. Denoting by λ the
wave-length of the radiation used, and by ε the
so-called numerical aperture, that is, the sine of
half the angle of convergence, the resolving power
of a microscope is given by the well-known expression
λ / 2ε. Even if the object is illuminated by
parallel light, so that the momentum h / λ of the
incident light quantum is known both as regards
magnitude and direction, the finite value of the
aperture will prevent an exact knowledge of the
recoil accompanying the scattering. Also, even if
the momentum of the particle were accurately
known before the scattering process, our knowledge
of the component of momentum parallel to
the focal plane after the observation would be
affected by an uncertainty amounting to 2εh / λ.
The product of the least inaccuracies with which
the positional co-ordinate and the component of
momentum in a definite direction can be ascertained
is therefore just given by formula (2). One
might perhaps expect that in estimating the accuracy
of determining the position, not only the
convergence but also the length of the wave-train
has to be taken into account, because the particle
could change its place during the finite time of
illumination. Due to the fact, however, that the
exact knowledge of the wave-length is immaterial
for the above estimate, it will be realised that for
any value of the aperture the wave-train can
always be taken so short that a change of position
of the particle during the time of observation may
be neglected in comparison to the lack of sharpness
inherent in the determination of position due to
the finite resolving power of the microscope.
In measuring momentum with the aid of the
Doppler effect—with due regard to the Compton
effect—one will employ a parallel wave-train. For
the accuracy, however, with which the change in
wave-length of the scattered radiation can be
measured the extent of the wave-train in the
direction of propagation is essential. If we assume
that the directions of the incident and scattered
radiation are parallel and opposite respectively to
the direction of the position co-ordinate and
momentum component to be measured, then
c λ/ 2l can be taken as a measure of the accuracy
in the determination of the velocity, where l
denotes the length of the wave-train. For simplicity,
we here have regarded the velocity of light
as large compared to the velocity of the particle.
If m represents the mass of the particle, then the
uncertainty attached to the value of the momentum
after observation is cmλ/ 2l. In this case the
magnitude of the recoil, 2h / λ, is sufficiently well
defined in order not to give rise to an appreciable
uncertainty in the value of the momentum of the
particle after observation. Indeed, the general
theory of the Compton effect allows us to compute
the momentum components in the direction of the
radiation before and after the recoil from the wavelengths
of the incident and scattered radiation.
Even if the positional co-ordinates of the particle
were accurately known in the beginning, our
knowledge of the position after observation nevertheless
will be affected by an uncertainty. Indeed,
on account of the impossibility of attributing a
definite instant to the recoil, we know the mean
velocity in the direction of observation during the
scattering process only with an accuracy 2h / λ.
The uncertainty in the position after observation
hence is 2hl / mcλ. Here, too, the product of the
inaccuracies in the measurement of position and
momentum is thus given by the general formula (2).
Just as in the case of the determination of
position, the time of the process of observation
for the determination of momentum may be
made as short as is desired if only the wavelength
of the radiation used is sufficiently small.
The fact that the recoil then gets larger does
not, as we have seen, affect the accuracy of
measurement. It should further be mentioned,
that in referring to the velocity of a particle as we
have here done repeatedly, the purpose has only
been to obtain a connexion with the ordinary
space-time description convenient in this ease. As
it appears already from the considerations of de
Broglie mentioned above, the concept of velocity
must always in the quantum theory be handled
with- caution. It will also be seen that an unambiguous
definition of this concept is excluded
by the quantum postulate. This is particularly
to be remembered when comparing the results of
successive observations. Indeed, the position of
an individual at two given moments can be
measured with any desired degree of accuracy;
but if, from such measurements, we would calculate
the velocity of the individual in the ordinary
way, it must be clearly realised that we are dealing
with an abstraction, from which no unambiguous
information concerning the previous or future
behaviour of the individual can be obtained.
According to the above considerations regarding
the possibilities of definition of the properties of
individuals, it will obviously make no difference
in the discussion of the accuracy of measurements
of position and momentum of a particle if collisions
with other material particles are considered instead
of scattering of radiation. In both cases we see
that the uncertainty in question equally affects
the description of the agency of measurement and
of the object. In fact, this uncertainty cannot
be avoided in a description of the behaviour of
individuals with respect to a co-ordinate system
fixed in the ordinary way by means of solid bodies
and unperturbable clocks. The experimental
devices—opening and closing of apertures, etc.—
are seen to permit only conclusions regarding the
space-time extension of the associated wave-fields.
In tracing observations back to our sensations,
once more regard has to be taken to the quantum
postulate in connexion with the perception of the
agency of observation, be it through its direct
action upon the eye or by means of suitable auxiliaries
such as photographic plates, Wilson clouds,
etc. It is easily seen, however, that the resulting
additional statistical element will not influence the
uncertainty in the description of the object. It
might even be conjectured that the arbitrariness
in what is regarded as object and what as agency
of observation would open up a possibility of
avoiding this uncertainty altogether. In connexion
with the measurement of the position of a
particle, one might, for example, ask whether the
momentum transmitted by the scattering could
not be determined by means of the conservation
theorem from a measurement of the change of
momentum of the microscope — including light
source and photographic plate — during the process
of observation.
Bohr famously defended the uncertainty principle against criticisms by Einstein in his "discussion with Einstein" at the 1927 Solvay conference.
A closer investigation shows,
however, that such a measurement is impossible,
if at the same time one wants to know the position
of the microscope with sufficient accuracy. In
fact, it follows from the experiences which have
found expression in the wave theory of matter,
that the position of the centre of gravity of a body
and its total momentum can only be defined
within the limits of reciprocal accuracy given by
relation (2).
Strictly speaking, the idea of observation belongs
to the causal space-time way of description. Due
to the general character of relation (2), however,
this idea can be consistently utilised also in the
quantum theory, if only the uncertainty expressed
through this relation is taken into account. As
remarked by Heisenberg, one may even obtain an
instructive illustration to the quantum theoretical
description of atomic (microscopic) phenomena by
comparing this uncertainty with the uncertainty,
due to imperfect measurements, inherently contained
in any observation as considered in the
ordinary description of natural phenomena. He
remarks on that occasion that even in the case of
macroscopic phenomena we may say, in a certain
sense, that they are created by repeated observations.
It must not be forgotten, however, that in
the classical theories any succeeding observation
permits a prediction of future events with ever-increasing
accuracy, because it improves our
knowledge of the initial state of the system.
According to the quantum theory, just the impossibility
of neglecting the interaction with the
agency of measurement means that every observation
introduces a new uncontrollable element.
Bohr seems ready to accept the idea that quantum theory is acausal. It makes clear the complementarity of space-time descriptions (now unsharp)
Indeed, it follows from the above considerations
that the measurement of the positional coordinates
of a particle is accompanied not only by
a finite change in the dynamical variables, but also
the fixation of its position means a complete rupture
in the causal description of its dynamical behaviour,
while the determination of its momentum
always implies a gap in the knowledge of its
spatial propagation. Just this situation brings
out most strikingly the complementary character
of the description of atomic phenomena which
appears as an inevitable consequence of the contrast
between the quantum postulate and the distinction
between object and agency of measurement,
inherent in our very idea of observation.
4. CORRESPONDENCE PRINCIPLE AND MATRIX
THEORY.
Hitherto we have only regarded certain general
features of the quantum problem. The situation
implies, however, that the main stress has to be
laid on the formulation of the laws governing the
interaction between the objects which we symbolise
by the abstractions of isolated particles and
radiation. Points of attack for this formulation
are presented in the first place by the problem of
atomic constitution. As is well known, it has been
possible here, by means of an elementary use of
classical concepts and in harmony with the quantum
postulate, to throw light on essential aspects of
experience. For example, the experiments regarding
the excitation of spectra by electronic impacts
and by radiation are adequately accounted for on
the assumption of discrete stationary states and
individual transition processes. This is primarily
due to the circumstance that in these questions
no closer description of the space-time behaviour
of the processes is required.
Here the contrast with the ordinary way of
description appears strikingly in the circumstance
that spectral lines, which on the classical view
would be ascribed to the same state of the atom,
will, according to the quantum postulate, correspond
to separate transition processes, between
which the excited atom has a choice. Notwithstanding
this contrast, however, a formal connexion
with the classical ideas could be obtained in the
limit, where the relative difference in the properties
of neighbouring stationary states vanishes
asymptotically and where in statistical applications
the discontinuities may be disregarded. Through
this connexion it was possible to a large extent to
interpret the regularities of spectra on the basis
of our ideas about the structure of the atom.
The aim of regarding the quantum theory as a
rational generalisation of the classical theories led
to the formulation of the so-called correspondence
principle. The utilisation of this principle for the
interpretation of spectroscopic results was based on
a symbolical application of classical electrodynamics,
in which the individual transition processes
were each associated with a harmonic in
the motion of the atomic particles to be expected
according to ordinary mechanics. Except in the
limit mentioned, where the relative difference
between adjacent stationary states may be neglected,
such a fragmentary application of the
classical theories could only in certain cases lead
to a strictly quantitative description of the phenomena.
Especially the connexion developed by
Ladenburg and Kramers between the classical
treatment of dispersion and the statistical laws
governing the radiative transition processes formulated
by Einstein should be mentioned here.
Although it was just Kramers' treatment of dispersion
that gave important hints for the rational
development of correspondence considerations, it
is only through the quantum theoretical methods
created in the last few years that the general
aims laid down in the principle mentioned have
obtained an adequate formulation.
As is known, the new development was commenced
in a fundamental paper by Heisenberg,
where he succeeded in emancipating himself completely
from the classical concept of motion by
replacing from the very start the ordinary kinematical
and mechanical quantities by symbols,
which refer directly to the individual processes
demanded by the quantum postulate.
and claims of causality (now acausal).
Although Heisenberg supports Bohr's original invention of stationary states, he declares them to be "unobservable." Schrödinger, by contrast, visualizes them as his wave functions. See §5.
This was
accomplished by substituting for the Fourier
development of a classical mechanical quantity
a matrix scheme, the elements of which symbolise
purely harmonic vibrations and are associated
with the possible transitions between stationary
states. By requiring that the frequencies ascribed
to the elements must always obey the combination
principle for spectral lines, Heisenberg
could introduce simple rules of calculation for the
symbols, which permit a direct quantum theoretical
transcription of the fundamental equations of
classical mechanics. This ingenious attack on the
dynamical problem of atomic theory proved itself
from the beginning to be an exceedingly powerful
and fertile method for interpreting quantitatively
the experimental results. Through the work of
Born and Jordan as well as of Dirac, the theory
was given a formulation which can compete with
classical mechanics as regards generality and
consistency. Especially the element characteristic
of the quantum theory, Planck's constant, appears
explicitly only in the algorithms to which the
symbols, the so-called matrices, are subjected.
In fact, matrices, which represent canonically
conjugated variables in the sense of the Hamiltonian
equations, do not obey the commutative
law of multiplication, but two such quantities, q
and p, have to fulfil the exchange rule
pq - qp = √-1 h / 2π, . . . (3)
Indeed, this exchange relation expresses strikingly
the symbolical character of the matrix formulation
of the quantum theory. The matrix theory has
often been called a calculus with directly observable
quantities. It must be remembered,
however, that the procedure described is limited
just to those problems, in which in applying the
quantum postulate the space-time description
may largely be disregarded, and the question of
observation in the proper sense therefore placed in
the background.
In pursuing further the correspondence of the
quantum laws with classical mechanics, the stress
placed on the statistical character of the quantum
theoretical description, which is brought in by the
quantum postulate, has been of fundamental
importance. Here the generalisation of the
symbolical method made by Dirac and Jordan
represented a great progress by making possible
the operation with matrices, which are not arranged
according to the stationary states, but where the
possible values of any set of variables may appear
as indices of the matrix elements. In analogy to
the interpretation considered in the original form
of the theory of the 'diagonal elements' connected
only with a single stationary state, as time averages
of the quantity to be represented, the general
transformation theory of matrices permits the
representation of such averages of a mechanical
quantity, in the calculation of which any set of
variables characterising the 'state' of the system
have given values, while the canonically conjugated
variables are allowed to take all possible values.
On the basis of the procedure developed by these
authors and in close connexion with ideas of
Born and Pauli, Heisenberg has in the paper
already cited above attempted a closer analysis
of the physical content of the quantum theory,
especially in view of the apparently paradoxical
character of the exchange relation (3). In this
connexion he has formulated the relation
Δq Δp ∼ h, . . . (4)
as the general expression for the maximum accuracy
with which two canonically conjugated variables
can simultaneously be observed. In this
way Heisenberg has been able to elucidate many
paradoxes appearing in the application of the
quantum postulate, and to a large extent to
demonstrate the consistency of the symbolic
method. In connexion with the complementary
nature of the quantum theoretical description, we
must, as already mentioned, constantly keep the
possibilities of definition as well as of observation
before the mind. For the discussion of just
this question the method of wave mechanics
developed by Schrödinger has, as we shall see,
proved of great help. It permits a general application
of the principle of superposition also
in the problem of interaction, thus offering an
immediate connexion with the above considerations
concerning radiation and free particles.
Below we shall return to the relation of wave
mechanics to the general formulation of the
quantum laws by means of the transformation
theory of matrices.
5. WAVE MECHANICS AND QUANTUM POSTULATE.
Already in his first considerations concerning
the wave theory of material particles, de Broglie
pointed out that the stationary states of an atom
may be visualised as an interference effect of the
phase wave associated with a bound electron.
It is true that this point of view at first did not, as
regards quantitative results, lead beyond the earlier
methods of quantum theory, to the development
of which Sommerfeld has contributed so essentially.
Schrödinger, however, succeeded in developing a
wave - theoretical method which has opened up
new aspects, and has proved to be of decisive
importance for the great progress in atomic
physics during the last years.
Where Heisenberg, and especially Pauli, discounted Bohr's visualization of the stationary states, Schrödinger found a "natural" source of Bohr's postulated quantum numbers in the nodes of his wave functions.
Indeed, the proper
vibrations of the Schrödinger wave equation have
been found to furnish a representation of the
stationary states of an atom meeting all requirements.
The energy of each state is connected with
the corresponding period of vibration according to
the general quantum relation (1). Furthermore,
the number of nodes in the various characteristic
vibrations gives a simple interpretation to the
concept of quantum number which was already
known from the older methods, but at first did not
seem to appear in the matrix formulation. In
addition, Schrödinger could associate with the
solutions of the wave equation a continuous distribution
of charge and current, which, if applied
to a characteristic vibration, represents the
electrostatic and magnetic properties of an atom
in the corresponding stationary state. Similarly,
the superposition of two characteristic solutions
corresponds to a continuous vibrating distribution
of electrical charge, which on classical electrodynamics
would give rise to an emission of radiation,
illustrating instructively the consequences of the
quantum postulate and the correspondence requirement
regarding the transition process between two
stationary states formulated in matrix mechanics.
Max Born's statistical interpretation of the particle wave function (based on Einstein's statistical relation between light waves and the probability of photons) was anathema to Schrödinger
Another application of the method of Schrödinger,
important for the further development, has been
made by Born in his investigation of the problem
of collisions between atoms and free electric
particles. In this connexion he succeeded in
obtaining a statistical interpretation of the wave
functions, allowing a calculation of the probability
of the individual transition processes required by
the quantum postulate. This includes a wave-mechanical
formulation of the adiabatic principle
of Ehrenfest, the fertility of which appears strikingly
in the promising investigations of Hund
on the problem of formation of molecules.
Schrödinger hoped to eliminate the discontinuous quantum jumps is Bohr's original quantum postulate, but then he would have no explanation for the observation of particles.
In view of these results, Schrödinger has expressed
the hope that the development of the
wave theory will eventually remove the irrational
element expressed by the quantum postulate and
open the way for a complete description of atomic
phenomena along the line of the classical theories.
In support of this view, Schrödinger, in a recent
paper (Ann. d. Phys., 83, p. 956; 1927), emphasises
the fact that the discontinuous exchange of energy
between atoms required by the quantum postulate,
from the point of view of the wave theory, is
replaced by a simple resonance phenomenon. In
particular, the idea of individual stationary states
would be an illusion and its applicability only an
illustration of the resonance mentioned. It must
be kept in mind, however, that just in the resonance
problem mentioned we are concerned with a closed
system which, according to the view presented here,
is not accessible to observation.
Wave mechanics and matrix mechanics might then be complementary in the same sense that wave and particle viewed as a duality are complementary.
In fact, wave
mechanics just as the matrix theory on this view
represents a symbolic transcription of the problem
of motion of classical mechanics adapted to the
requirements of quantum theory and only to be
interpreted by an explicit use of the quantum
postulate. Indeed, the two formulations of the
interaction problem might be said to be complementary
in the same sense as the wave and
particle idea in the description of the free individuals.
The apparent contrast in the utilisation
of the energy concept in the two theories is just
connected with this difference in the starting-point.
The fundamental difficulties opposing a space-time
description of a system of particles in interaction
appear at once from the inevitability of the
superposition principle in the description of the
behaviour of individual particles. Already for a
free particle the knowledge of energy and momentum
excludes, as we have seen, the exact
knowledge of its space-time co-ordinates. This
implies that an immediate utilisation of the concept
of energy in connexion with the classical idea of
the potential energy of the system is excluded.
In the Schrödinger wave equation these difficulties
are avoided by replacing the classical expression
of the Hamiltonian by a differential operator by
means of the relation
p = √-1 ( h / 2π ) δ / δq, . . . (5)
where p denotes a generalised component of
momentum and q the canonically conjugated
variable. Hereby the negative value of the energy
is regarded as conjugated to the time. So far, in
the wave equation, time and space as well as
energy and momentum are utilised in a purely
formal way.
The symbolical character of Schrödinger's
method appears not only from the circumstance
that its simplicity, similarly to that of the matrix
theory, depends essentially upon the use of
imaginary arithmetic quantities. But above all
there can be no question of an immediate connexion
with our ordinary conceptions because the
'geometrical' problem represented by the wave
equation is associated with the so-called co-ordinate
space, the number of dimensions of which is equal to
the number of degrees of freedom of the system,
and hence in general greater than the number of
dimensions of ordinary space. Further, Schrödinger's
formulation of the interaction problem,
just as the formulation offered by matrix theory,
involves a neglect of the finite velocity of propagation
of the forces claimed by relativity theory.
On the whole, it would scarcely seem justifiable,
in the case of the interaction problem, to demand
a visualisation by means of ordinary space-time
pictures. In fact, all our knowledge concerning
the internal properties of atoms is derived from
experiments on their radiation or collision reactions,
such that the interpretation of experimental facts
ultimately depends on the abstractions of radiation
in free space, and free material particles. Hence,
our whole space-time view of physical phenomena,
as well as the definition of energy and momentum,
depends ultimately upon these abstractions. In
judging the applications of these auxiliary ideas
we should only demand inner consistency, in which
connexion special regard has to be paid to the
possibilities of definition and observation.
Bohr likes Schrödinger's visualization of the stationary states in his quantum postulate. But we must replace space-time descriptions - sharply defined mass points - with wave-packet superpositions of wave functions.
In the characteristic vibrations of Schrödinger's
wave equation we have, as mentioned, an adequate
representation of the stationary states of an atom
allowing an unambiguous definition of the energy
of the system by means of the general quantum
relation (1). This entails, however, that in the
interpretation of observations, a fundamental
renunciation regarding the space-time description
is unavoidable. In fact, the consistent application
of the concept of stationary states excludes, as we
shall see, any specification regarding the behaviour
of the separate particles in the atom. In problems
where a description of this behaviour is essential,
we are bound to use the general solution of the
wave equation which is obtained by superposition
of characteristic solutions. We meet here
with a complementarity of the possibilities of
definition quite analogous to that which we have
considered earlier in connexion with the properties
of light and free material particles. Thus,
while the definition of energy and momentum of
individuals is attached to the idea of a harmonic
elementary wave, every space-time feature of the
description of phenomena is, as we have seen, based
on a consideration of the interferences taking place
inside a group of such elementary waves. Also in
the present case the agreement between the possibilities
of observation and those of definition can
be directly shown.
According to the quantum postulate any observation
regarding the behaviour of the electron
in the atom will be accompanied by a change in
the state of the atom. As stressed by Heisenberg,
this change will, in the case of atoms in stationary
states of low quantum number, consist in general
in the ejection of the electron from the atom. A description
of the 'orbit' of the electron in the atom
with the aid of subsequent observations is hence
impossible in such a case. This is connected with
the circumstance that from characteristic vibrations
with only a few nodes no wave packages can
be built up which would even approximately
represent the 'motion' of a particle. The complementary
nature of the description, however,
appears particularly in that the use of observations
concerning the behaviour of particles in the atom
rests on the possibility of neglecting, during the
process of observation, the interaction between
the particles, thus regarding them as free. This
requires, however, that the duration of the process
is short compared with the natural periods of the
atom, which again means that the uncertainty in
the knowledge of the energy transferred in the
process is large compared to the energy differences
between neighbouring stationary states.
In judging the possibilities of observation it must,
on the whole, be kept in mind that the wave
mechanical solutions can be visualised only in so
far as they can be described with the aid of the
concept of free particles. Here the difference
between classical mechanics and the quantum
theoretical treatment of the problem of interaction
appears most strikingly. In the former such
a restriction is unnecessary, because the 'particles '
are here endowed with an immediate 'reality,'
independently of their being free or bound. This
situation is particularly important in connexion
with the consistent utilisation of Schrödinger's
electric density as a measure of the probability
for electrons being present within given space
regions of the atom.
Probabilites for particles in a matter-wave field (Born) are analogous to the probabilities for photons in a radiation field (Einstein).
Remembering the restriction
mentioned, this interpretation is seen to be a
simple consequence of the assumption that the
probability of the presence of a free electron is
expressed by the electric density associated with
the wave-field in a similar way to that by which the
probability of the presence of a light quantum is
given by the energy density of the radiation.
As already mentioned, the means for a general
consistent utilisation of the classical concepts in
the quantum theory have been created through
the transformation theory of Dirac and Jordan,
by the aid of which Heisenberg has formulated his
general uncertainty relation (4). In this theory
also the Schrödinger wave equation has obtained
an instructive application. In fact, the characteristic
solutions of this equation appear as auxiliary
functions which define a transformation from
matrices with indices representing the energy values
of the system to other matrices, the indices of
which are the possible values of the space coordinates.
It is also of interest in this connexion
to mention that Jordan and Klein (Zeitsch. f.
Phys., 45, 751 ; 1927) have recently arrived at the
formulation of the problem of interaction expressed
by the Schrödinger wave equation, taking as
starting-point the wave representation of individual
particles and applying a symbolic method closely
related to the deep-going treatment of the radiation
problem developed by Dirac from the point of view
of the matrix theory, to which we shall return
below.
6. REALITY OF STATIONARY STATES.
In the conception of stationary states we are,
as mentioned, concerned with a characteristic
application of the quantum postulate. By its very
nature this conception means a complete renunciation
as regards a time description. From
the point of view taken here, just this renunciation
forms the necessary condition for an unambiguous
definition of the energy of the atom. Moreover,
the conception of a stationary state involves,
strictly speaking, the exclusion of all interactions
with individuals not belonging to the system. The
fact that such a closed system is associated with
a particular energy value may be considered as
an immediate expression for the claim of causality
contained in the theorem of conservation of energy.
This circumstance justifies the assumption of the
supra-mechanical stability of the stationary states,
according to which the atom, before as well as after
an external influence, always will be found in a
well-defined state, and which forms the basis for
the use of the quantum postulate in problems
concerning atomic structure.
In a judgment of the well-known paradoxes
which this assumption entails for the description
of collision and radiation reactions, it is essential
to consider the limitations of the possibilities of
definition of the reacting free individuals, which is
expressed by relation (2). In fact, if the definition
of the energy of the reacting individuals is to be
accurate to such a degree as to entitle us to speak
of conservation of energy during the reaction, it
is necessary, according to this relation, to coordinate
to the reaction a time interval long
compared to the vibration period associated with
the transition process, and connected with the
energy difference between the stationary states
according to relation (1). This is particularly
to be remembered when considering the passage
of swiftly moving particles through an atom.
According to the ordinary kinematics, the effective
duration of such a passage would be very small
as compared with the natural periods of the atom,
and it seemed impossible to reconcile the principle
of conservation of energy with the assumption of
the stability of stationary states (cf. Zeits. f.
Phys., 34, 142 ; 1925). In the wave representation,
however, the time of reaction is immediately
connected with the accuracy of the knowledge of
the energy of the colliding particle, and hence
there can never be the possibility of a contradiction
with the law of conservation. In connexion with
the discussion of paradoxes of the kind mentioned,
Campbell (Phil. Mag., i. 1106; 1926) suggested
the view that the conception of time itself may
be essentially statistical in nature. From the
view advanced here, according to which the
foundation of space-time description is offered by
the abstraction of free individuals, a fundamental
distinction between time and space, however,
would seem to be excluded by the relativity requirement.
The singular position of the time in problems
concerned with stationary states is, as we have
seen, due to the special nature of such problems.
Unlike complex emergent biological systems, elementary physical particles have no "history." Information about the previous states of all atoms is needed for deterministic theories that reduce biology to physics.
The application of the conception of stationary
states demands that in any observation, say by
means of collision or radiation reactions, permitting
a distinction between different stationary states, we
are entitled to disregard the previous history of the
atom. The fact that the symbolical quantum theory
methods ascribe a particular phase to each stationary
state the value of which depends upon the
previous history of the atom, would for the first
moment seem to contradict the very idea of
stationary states. As soon as we are really concerned
with a time problem, however, the consideration
of a strictly closed system is excluded. The
use of simply harmonic proper vibrations in the
interpretation of observations means, therefore,
only a suitable idealisation which in a more rigorous
discussion must always be replaced by a group
of harmonic vibrations, distributed over a finite
frequency interval. Now, as already mentioned,
it is a general consequence of the superposition
principle that it has no sense to co-ordinate a
phase value to the group as a whole, in the same
manner as may be done for each elementary wave
constituting the group.
This inobservability of the phase, well known
from the theory of optical instruments, is brought
out in a particularly simple manner in a discussion
of the Stern-Gerlach experiment, so important for
the investigation of the properties of single atoms.
As pointed out by Heisenberg, atoms with different
orientation in the field may only be separated if
the deviation of the beam is larger than the diffraction
at the slit of the de Broglie waves representing
the translational motion of the atoms.
This condition means, as a simple calculation shows,
that the product of the time of passage of the
atom through the field, and the uncertainty due
to the finite width of the beam of its energy in the
field, is at least equal to the quantum of action.
This result was considered by Heisenberg as a
support of relation (2) as regards the reciprocal
uncertainties of energy and time values. It would
seem, however, that here we are not simply dealing
with a measurement of the energy of the atom at
a given time. But since the period of the proper
vibrations of the atom in the field is connected
with the total energy by relation (1), we realise
that the condition for separability mentioned
just means the loss of the phase. This circumstance
removes also the apparent contradictions,
arising in certain problems concerning the
coherence of resonance radiation, which have been
discussed frequently, and were also considered by
Heisenberg.
To consider an atom as a closed system, as
we have done above, means to neglect the spontaneous
emission of radiation which even in the
absence of external influences puts an upper limit
to the lifetime of the stationary states. The fact
that this neglect is justified in many applications
is connected with the circumstance that the
coupling between the atom and the radiation
field, which is to be expected on classical electrodynamics,
is in general very small compared to the
coupling between the particles in the atom. It is,
in fact, possible in a description of the state of
an atom to a considerable extent to neglect the
reaction of radiation, thus disregarding the unsharpness
in the energy values connected with the
lifetime of the stationary states according to
relation (2) (cf. Proc. Camb. Phil. Soc., 1924
(Supplement), or Zeits. f. Phys., 13, 117; 1923).
This is the reason why it is possible to draw
conclusions concerning the properties of radiation
by using classical electrodynamics.
The treatment of the radiation problem by the
new quantum theoretical methods meant to begin
with just a quantitative formulation of this correspondence
consideration. This was the very starting-point
of the original considerations of Heisenberg.
It may also be mentioned that an instructive analysis
of Schrödinger's treatment of the radiation phenomena
from the point of view of the correspondence
principle has been recently given by Klein (Zeits.
f. Phys., 41,707; 1927). In the more rigorous form
of the theory developed by Dirac (Proc. Roy. Soc.,
A, vol. 114, p. 243 ; 1927) the radiation field itself
is included in the closed system under consideration.
Thus it became possible in a rational way to take
account of the individual character of radiation
demanded by the quantum theory and to build
up a dispersion theory, in which the final width
of the spectral lines is taken into consideration.
The renunciation regarding space-time pictures
characterising this treatment would seem to offer
a striking indication of the complementary character
of the quantum theory. This is particularly
to be borne in mind in judging the radical departure
from the causal description of Nature met with in
radiation phenomena, to which we have referred
above in connexion with the excitation of spectra.
In view of the asymptotic connexion of atomic
properties with classical electrodynamics, demanded
by the correspondence principle, the reciprocal
exclusion of the conception of stationary
states and the description of the behaviour of
individual particles in the atom might be regarded
as a difficulty. In fact, the connexion in question
means that in the limit of large quantum
numbers where the relative difference between
adjacent stationary states vanishes asymptotically,
mechanical pictures of electronic motion may be
rationally utilised. It must be emphasised, however,
that this connexion cannot be regarded as a
gradual transition towards classical theory in the
sense that the quantum postulate would lose its
significance for high quantum numbers. On the
contrary, the conclusions obtained from the correspondence
principle with the aid of classical
pictures depend just upon the assumptions that
the conception of stationary states and of individual
transition processes are maintained even in this limit.
This question offers a particularly instructive
example for the application of the new methods.
As shown by Schrödinger (Naturwiss., 14, 664 ;
1926), it is possible, in the limit mentioned, by
superposition of proper vibrations to construct
wave groups small in comparison to the ' size ' of
the atom, the propagation of which indefinitely
approaches the classical picture of moving material
particles, if the quantum numbers are chosen
sufficiently large. In the special ease of a simple
harmonic vibrator, he was able to show that
such wave groups will keep together even for any
length of time, and will oscillate to and fro in a
manner corresponding to the classical picture of
the motion. This circumstance Schrödinger has
regarded as a support of his hope of constructing a
pure wave theory without referring to the quantum
postulate. As emphasised by Heisenberg, the
simplicity of the case of the oscillator, however, is
exceptional and intimately connected with the
harmonic nature of the corresponding classical
motion. Nor is there in this example any possibility
for an asymptotical approach towards the problem
of free particles. In general, the wave group will
gradually spread over the whole region of the atom,
and the 'motion' of a bound electron can only
be followed during a number of periods, which is
of the order of magnitude of the quantum numbers
associated with the proper vibrations. This question
has been more closely investigated in a recent
paper by Darwin (Proc. Roy. Soc, A, vol. 117,
258; 1927), which contains a number of instructive
examples of the behaviour of wave groups.
From the viewpoint of the matrix theory a treatment
of analogous problems has been carried out
by Kennard (Zeits. f. Phys., 47, 326 ; 1927).
Here again we meet with the contrast between
the wave theory superposition principle and the
assumption of the individuality of particles with
which we have been concerned already in the
case of free particles. At the same time the
asymptotical connexion with the classical theory,
to which a distinction between free and bound
particles is unknown, offers the possibility of a
particularly simple illustration of the above considerations
regarding the consistent utilisation of
the concept of stationary states. As we have seen,
the identification of a stationary state by means of
collision or radiation reactions implies a gap in the
time description, which is at least of the order of
magnitude of the periods associated with transitions
between stationary states. Now, in the limit of high
quantum numbers these periods may be interpreted
as periods of revolution. Thus we see at once
that no causal connexion can be obtained between
observations leading to the fixation of a stationary
state and earlier observations on the behaviour of
the separate particles in the atom.
Today quantum mechanics can not only observe "individual particles," but control their transitions between stationary states with exquisite accuracy.
Summarising, it might be said that the concepts
of stationary states and individual transition processes
within their proper field of application
possess just as much or as little 'reality' as the
very idea of individual particles. In both cases
we are concerned with a demand of causality
complementary to the space-time description, the
adequate application of which is limited only by
the restricted possibilities of definition and of
observation.
7. THE PROBLEM OF THE ELEMENTARY
PARTICLES.
When due regard is taken of the complementary
feature required by the quantum postulate, it
seems, in fact, possible with the aid of the symbolic
methods to build up a consistent theory of
atomic phenomena, which may be considered as a
rational generalisation of the causal space-time
description of classical physics. This view does
not mean, however, that classical electron theory
may be regarded simply as the limiting case of a
vanishing quantum of action. Indeed, the connexion
of the latter theory with experience is
based on assumptions which can scarcely be
separated from the group of problems of the
quantum theory. A hint in this direction was
already given by the well-known difficulties met
with in the attempts to account for the individuality
of ultimate electrical particles on
general mechanical and electrodynamical principles.
In this respect also the general relativity
theory of gravitation has not fulfilled expectations.
A satisfactory solution of the problems
touched upon would seem to be possible only by
means of a rational quantum-theoretical transcription
of the general field theory, in which the
ultimate quantum of electricity has found its
natural position as an expression of the feature of
individuality characterising the quantum theory.
Recently Klein (Zeits. f. Phys., 46, 188; 1927) has
directed attention to the possibility of connecting
this problem with the five-dimensional unified
representation of electromagnetism and gravitation
proposed by Kaluza. In fact, the conservation
of electricity appears in this theory as an
analogue to the conservation theorems for energy
and momentum. Just as these concepts are complementary
to the space-time description, the
appropriateness of the ordinary four-dimensional
description as well as its symbolical utilisation in
the quantum theory would, as Klein emphasises,
seem to depend essentially on the circumstance
that in this description electricity always appears
in well-defined units, the conjugated fifth dimension
being as a consequence not open to observation.
Quite apart from these unsolved deep-going
problems, the classical electron theory up to the
present time has been the guide for a further
development of the correspondence description in
connexion with the idea first advanced by Compton
that the ultimate electrical particles, besides their
mass and charge, are endowed with a magnetic
moment due to an angular momentum determined
by the quantum of action. This assumption, introduced
with striking success by Goudsmit and
Uhlenbeck into the discussion of the origin of the
anomalous Zeeman effect, has proved most fruitful
in connexion with the new methods, as
shown especially by Heisenberg and Jordan. One
might say, indeed, that the hypothesis of the
magnetic electron, together with the resonance
problem elucidated by Heisenberg (Zeits. f. Phys.,
41, 239; 1927), which occurs in the quantum-theoretical
description of the behaviour of atoms
with several electrons, have brought the correspondence
interpretation of the spectral laws and
the periodic system to a certain degree of completion.
The principles underlying this attack have
even made it possible to draw conclusions regarding
the properties of atomic nuclei. Thus Dennison
(Proc. Roy. Soc., A, vol. 115, 483; 1927), in
connexion with ideas of Heisenberg and Hund,
has succeeded recently in a very interesting way
in showing how the explanation of the specific
heat of hydrogen, hitherto beset with difficulties,
can be harmonised with the assumption
that the proton is endowed with a moment of
momentum of the same magnitude as that of the
electron. Due to its larger mass, however, a
magnetic moment much smaller than that of the
electron must be associated with the proton.
The insufficiency of the methods hitherto developed
as concerns the problem of the elementary
particles appears in the questions just mentioned
from the fact that they do not allow of an unambiguous
explanation of the difference in the
behaviour of the electric elementary particles and
the 'individuals' symbolised through the conception
of fight quanta expressed in the so-called
exclusion principle formulated by Pauli. In fact,
we meet in this principle, so important for the
problem of atomic structure as well as for the
recent development of statistical theories, with
one among several possibilities, each of which
fulfils the correspondence requirement. Moreover,
the difficulty of satisfying the relativity requirement
in quantum theory appears in a particularly
striking fight in connexion with the problem of
the magnetic electron. Indeed, it seemed not
possible to bring the promising attempts made
by Darwin and Pauli in generalising the new
methods to cover this problem naturally, in
connexion with the relativity kinematical consideration
of Thomas so fundamental for the
interpretation of experimental results. Quite
recently, however, Dirac (Proc. of the Roy. Soc.,
A, 117, 610; 1928) has been able successfully
to attack the problem of the magnetic electron
through a new ingenious extension of the symbolical
method and so to satisfy the relativity requirement
without abandoning the agreement with
spectral evidence. In this attack not only the
imaginary complex quantities appearing in the
earlier procedures are involved, but his fundamental
equations themselves contain quantities
of a still higher degree of complexity, that are
represented by matrices.
Already the formulation of the relativity argument
implies essentially the union of the spacetime
co-ordination and the demand of causality
characterising the classical theories. In the
adaptation of the relativity requirement to the
quantum postulate we must therefore be prepared
to meet with a renunciation as to visualisation in
the ordinary sense going still further than in the
formulation of the quantum laws considered here.
Bohr is disingenuous. He has for decades denied Einstein's extraordinary insights into light quanta and the wave-particle duality that is the core of complementarity.
Indeed, we find ourselves here on the very path
taken by Einstein of adapting our modes of perception
borrowed from the sensations to the gradually
deepening knowledge of the laws of Nature. The
hindrances met with on this path originate above
all in the fact that, so to say, every word in the
language refers to our ordinary perception. In
the quantum theory we meet this difficulty at once
in the question of the inevitability of the feature
of irrationality characterising the quantum postulate.
I hope, however, that the idea of complementarity
is suited to characterise the situation,
which bears a deep-going analogy to the general
difficulty in the formation of human ideas, inherent
in the distinction between subject and object.
For Teachers
For Scholars
|