Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Dupré John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker U.T.Place Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars David Shiang Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong Peter Slezak J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing C. S. Unnikrishnan Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium |
Albert Einstein - Reply to Criticisms
REMARKS CONCERNING THE ESSAYS BROUGHT TOGETHER IN THIS CO-OPERATIVE VOLUME
By way of introduction I must remark that it was not easy
for me to do justice to the task of expressing myself concerning the essays contained in this volume. The reason lies in
the fact that the essays refer to entirely too many subjects,
which, at the present state of our knowledge, are only loosely
connected with each other. I first attempted to discuss the essays
individually. However, I abandoned this procedure because
nothing even approximately homogeneous resulted, so that the
reading of it could hardly have been either useful or enjoyable.
I finally decided, therefore, to order these remarks, as far as
possible, according to topical considerations.
Furthermore, after some vain efforts, I discovered that the
mentality which underlies a few of the essays differs so radically
from my own, that I am incapable of saying anything useful
about them. This is not to be interpreted that I regard those
essays — insofar as their content is at all meaningful to me —
less highly than I do those which lie closer to my own ways of
thinking, to which [latter] I dedicate the following remarks.
To begin with I refer to the essays of Wolfgang Pauli and
Max Born. They describe the content of my work concerning
quanta and statistics in general in their inner consistency and
in their participation in the evolution of physics during the last
half century. It is meritorious that they have done this: For
only those who have successfully wrestled with the problematic
situations of their own age can have a deep insight into those
situations} unlike the later historian, who finds it difficult to make
abstractions from those concepts and views which appear to his
generation as established, or even as self-evident. Both authors
[p.666] deprecate the fact that I reject the basic idea of contemporary
statistical quantum theory, insofar as I do not believe that this
fundamental concept will provide a useful basis for the whole
of physics. More of this later.
I now come to what is probably the most interesting subject
which absolutely must be discussed in connection with the detailed arguments of my highly esteemed colleagues Born, Pauli,
Heitler, Bohr, and Margenau. They are all firmly convinced
that the riddle of the double nature of all corpuscles (corpuscular and undulatory character) has in essence found its final
solution in the statistical quantum theory.
Here "complete" means less than simultaneous accurate values of position and momentum. For Einstein, this is still "incomplete."
On the strength of
the successes of this theory they consider it proved that a theoretically complete description of a system can, in essence, involve only statistical assertions concerning the measurable quantities of this system. They are apparently all of the opinion
that Heisenberg's indeterminacy-relation (the correctness of
which is, from my own point of view, rightfully regarded as
finally demonstrated) is essentially prejudicial in favor of the
character of all thinkable reasonable physical theories in the
mentioned sense. In what follows I wish to adduce reasons
which keep me from falling in line with the opinion of almost
all contemporary theoretical physicists.
Einstein's major criticism of quantum theory.
I am, in fact, firmly convinced that the essentially statistical character of contemporary
quantum theory is solely to be ascribed to the fact that this
[theory] operates with an incomplete description of physical systems.
Above all, however, the reader should be convinced that I
fully recognize the very important progress which the statistical
quantum theory has brought to theoretical physics.
If it is statistical, then it is incomplete
Einstein endorses the statistical quantum theory. It explains the wave-particle duality he called for in 1909. It is a complete theory, up to the indeterminacy relation. Any future theory will probably incorporate this quantum theory.
In the field
of mechanical problems — i.e., wherever it is possible to consider
the interaction of structures and of their parts with sufficient
accuracy by postulating a potential energy between material
points — [this theory] even now presents a system which, in its
closed character, correctly describes the empirical relations between statable phenomena as they were theoretically to be expected. This theory is until now the only one which unites the
corpuscular and undulatory dual character of matter in a
logically satisfactory fashion; and the (testable) relations,
[p.667]
which are contained in it, are, within the natural limits fixed
by the indeterminacy-relation, complete. The formal relations
which are given in this theory — i.e., its entire mathematical
formalism — will probably have to be contained, in the form of
logical inferences, in every useful future theory.
What does not satisfy me in that theory, from the standpoint of principle, is its attitude towards that which appears to
me to be the programmatic aim of all physics: the complete description of any (individual) real situation (as it supposedly
exists irrespective of any act of observation or substantiation).
Whenever the positivistically inclined modern physicist hears
such a formulation his reaction is that of a pitying smile. He
says to himself: "there we have the naked formulation of a
metaphysical prejudice, empty of content, a prejudice, moreover, the conquest of which constitutes the major epistemological achievement of physicists within the last quarter-century.
Has any man ever perceived a 'real physical situation'? How is
it possible that a reasonable person could today still believe
that he can refute our essential knowledge and understanding
by drawing up such a bloodless ghost?" Patience! The above
laconic characterization was not meant to convince anyone; it
was merely to indicate the point of view around which the following elementary considerations freely group themselves. In
doing this I shall proceed as follows: I shall first of all show in
simple special cases what seems essential to me, and then I shall
make a few remarks about some more general ideas which are
involved.
We consider as a physical system, in the first instance, a radioactive atom of definite average decay time, which is practically
exactly localized at a point of the co-ordinate system. The
radioactive process consists in the emission of a (comparatively
light) particle. For the sake of simplicity we neglect the motion of the residual atom after the disintegration-process. Then
it is possible for us, following Gamow, to replace the rest of
the atom by a space of atomic order of magnitude, surrounded
by a closed potential energy barrier which, at a time t = 0,
encloses the particle to be emitted. The radioactive process
thus schematized is then, as is well known, to be described — in
[p.668]
the sense of elementary quantum mechanics — by a ψ-function
in three dimensions, which at the time t = 0 is different from
zero only inside of the barrier, but which, for positive times,
expands into the outer space. This ψ-function yields the probability that the particle, at some chosen instant, is actually in a
chosen part of space (i.e., is actually found there by a measurement of position). On the other hand, the ψ-function does not
imply any assertion concerning the time instant of the disintegration of the radioactive atom.
Now we raise the question: Can this theoretical description
be taken as the complete description of the disintegration of a
single individual atom? The immediately plausible answer is:
No.
But in his autobiography, he was doubtful
Compare Einstein in 1917: It is "a weakness in the theory..., that it leaves time and direction of elementary processes to chance (Zufall, ibid.)."
Einstein is right that statistical quantum mechanics describes only ensembles of systems.
For one is, first of all, inclined to assume that the individual atom decays at a definite time; however, such a definite time-value is not implied in the description by the ψ-function.
If, therefore, the individual atom has a definite disintegration-time, then as regards the individual atom its description by
means of the ψ-function must be interpreted as an incomplete
description. In this case the ψ-function is to be taken as the
description, not of a singular system, but of an ideal ensemble
of systems. In this case one is driven to the conviction that a
complete description of a single system should, after all, be
possible; but for such complete description there is no room in
the conceptual world of statistical quantum theory.
To this the quantum theorist will reply: This consideration
stands and falls with the assertion that there actually is such
a thing as a definite time of disintegration of the individual
atom (an instant of time existing independently of any observation). But this assertion is, from my point of view, not merely arbitrary but actually meaningless. The assertion of the
existence of a definite time-instant for the disintegration makes
sense only if I can in principle determine this time-instant empirically. Such an assertion, however, (which, finally, leads
to the attempt to prove the existence of the particle outside of
the force barrier), involves a definite disturbance of the system
in which we are interested; so that the result of the determination does not permit a conclusion concerning the status of the
undisturbed system. The supposition, therefore, that a radio
[p.669]
active atom has a definite disintegration-time is not justified by
anything whatsoever} it is, therefore, not demonstrated either
that the ψ-function can not be conceived as a complete description of the individual system. The entire alleged difficulty
proceeds from the fact that one postulates something not observable as "real." (This the answer of the quantum theorist.)
What I dislike in this kind of argumentation is the basic
positivistic attitude, which from my point of view is untenable,
and which seems to me to come to the same thing as Berkeley's
principle, esse est percipi. "Being" is always something which
is mentally constructed by us, that is, something which we freely posit (in the logical sense). The justification of such constructs does not lie in their derivation from what is given by
the senses. Such a type of derivation (in the sense of logical
deducibility) is nowhere to be had, not even in the domain
of pre-scientific thinking. The justification of the constructs,
which represent "reality" for us, lies alone in their quality of
making intelligible what is sensorily given (the vague character
of this expression is here forced upon me by my striving for
brevity). Applied to the specifically chosen example this consideration tells us the following:
One may not merely ask: "Does a definite time instant for
the transformation of a single atom exist?" but rather: "Is it,
within the framework of our theoretical total construction, reasonable to posit the existence of a definite point of time for the
transformation of a single atom?" One may not even ask what
this assertion means. One can only ask whether such a proposition, within the framework of the chosen conceptual system —
with a view to its ability to grasp theoretically what is empirically
given — is reasonable or not.
Insofar, then, as a quantum-theoretician takes the position that the description by means of a ψ-function refers
only to an ideal systematic totality but in no wise to the individual system, he may calmly assume a definite point of time
for the transformation. But, if he represents the assumption
that his description by way of the ψ-function is to be taken
as the complete description of the individual system, then he
must reject the postulation of a specific decay-time. He can
[p.670] justifiably point to the fact that a determination of the instant
of disintegration is not possible on an isolated system, but would
require disturbances of such a character that they must not be
neglected in the critical examination of the situation. It would,
for example, not be possible to conclude from the empirical
statement that the transformation has already taken place, that
this would have been the case if the disturbances of the system had not taken place.
As far as I know, it was E. Schrödinger who first called
attention to a modification of this consideration, which shows an
interpretation of this type to be impracticable. Rather than
considering a system which comprises only a radioactive atom
(and its process of transformation), one considers a system
which includes also the means for ascertaining the radioactive
transformation — for example, a Geiger-counter with automatic
registration-mechanism. Let this latter include a registration-
strip, moved by a clockwork, upon which a mark is made by
tripping the counter. True, from the point of view of quantum
mechanics this total system is very complex and its configuration space is of very high dimension. But there is in principle
no objection to treating this entire system from the standpoint
of quantum mechanics. Here too the theory determines the
probability of each configuration of all its co-ordinates for every
time instant. If one considers all configurations of the coordinates, for a time large compared with the average decay-time of the radioactive atom, there will be (at most) one such
registration-mark on the paper strip. To each co-ordinate-configuration corresponds a definite position of the mark on the
paper strip. But, inasmuch as the theory yields only the relative probability of the thinkable co-ordinate-configurations, it
also offers only relative probabilities for the positions of the
mark on the paperstrip, but no definite location for this mark.
In this consideration the location of the mark on the strip
plays the role played in the original consideration by the time
of the disintegration. The reason for the introduction of the
system supplemented by the registration-mechanism lies in the
following. The location of the mark on the registration-strip
concepts, in contradistinction to the instant of disintegration of
a single atom. If we attempt [to work with] the interpretation
that the quantum-theoretical description is to be understood
as a complete description of the individual system, we are
forced to the interpretation that the location of the mark on
the strip is nothing which belongs to the system per se, but
that the existence of that location is essentially dependent upon
the carrying out of an observation made on the registration-strip. Such an interpretation is certainly by no means absurd
from a purely logical standpoint; yet there is hardly likely
to be anyone who would be inclined to consider it seriously.
For, in the macroscopic sphere it simply is considered certain
that one must adhere to the program of a realistic description
in space and time; whereas in the sphere of microscopic situations one is more readily inclined to give up, or at least to modify, this program.
Einstein is right that statistical quantum theory does not produce a "complete" description. But missing information is not the result of human ignorance as in classical statistical mechanics
This discussion was only to bring out the following. One
arrives at very implausible theoretical conceptions, if one attempts to maintain the thesis that the statistical quantum theory
is in principle capable of producing a complete description of
an individual physical system. On the other hand, those difficulties of theoretical interpretation disappear, if one views the
quantum-mechanical description as the description of ensembles
of systems.
I reached this conclusion as the result of quite different types
of considerations. I am convinced that everyone who will take
the trouble to carry through such reflections conscientiously
will find himself finally driven to this interpretation of quantum-theoretical description (the ψ-function is to be understood as the description not of a single system but of an ensemble of
systems).
Roughly stated the conclusion is this: Within the framework of statistical quantum theory there is no such thing as a
complete description of the individual system. More cautiously
it might be put as follows: The attempt to conceive the quantum-theoretical description as the complete description of the
individual systems leads to unnatural theoretical interpretations, which become immediately unnecessary if one accepts the
[p.672]
interpretation that the description refers to ensembles of systems and not to individual systems. In that case the whole
"egg-walking" performed in order to avoid the "physically
real" becomes superfluous. There exists, however, a simple
psychological reason for the fact that this most nearly obvious
interpretation is being shunned. For if the statistical quantum
theory does not pretend to describe the individual system (and
its development in time) completely, it appears unavoidable to
look elsewhere for a complete description of the individual system^ in doing so it would be clear from the very beginning
that the elements of such a description are not contained within
the conceptual scheme of the statistical quantum theory. With
this one would admit that, in principle, this scheme could not
serve as the basis of theoretical physics. Assuming the success
of efforts to accomplish a complete physical description, the
statistical quantum theory would, within the framework of
future physics, take an approximately analogous position to the
statistical mechanics within the framework of classical mechanics. I am rather firmly convinced that the development of
theoretical physics will be of this type; but the path will be
lengthy and difficult.
I now imagine a quantum theoretician who may even admit
that the quantum-theoretical description refers to ensembles of
systems and not to individual systems, but who, nevertheless,
clings to the idea that the type of description of the statistical
quantum theory will, in its essential features, be retained in
the future. He may argue as follows: True, I admit that the
quantum-theoretical description is an incomplete description
of the individual system. I even admit that a complete theoretical description is, in principle, thinkable. But I consider it
proven that the search for such a complete description would
be aimless. For the lawfulness of nature is thus constituted
that the laws can be completely and suitably formulated within
the framework of our incomplete description.
To this I can only reply as follows: Your point of view —
taken as theoretical possibility — is incontestable. For me, however, the expectation that the adequate formulation of the
universal laws involves the use of all conceptual elements
[p.673]
which are necessary for a complete description, is more natural.
It is furthermore not at all surprising that, by using an incomplete description, (in the main) only statistical statements can
be obtained out of such description. If it should be possible to
move forward to a complete description, it is likely that the
laws would represent relations among all the conceptual elements
of this description which, per se, have nothing to do with statistics.
A few more remarks of a general nature concerning concepts „
and [also] concerning the insinuation that a concept — for example that of the real — is something metaphysical (and therefore to be rejected). A basic conceptual distinction, which is a necessary prerequisite of scientific and pre-scientific thinking,
is the distinction between "sense-impressions" (and the recollection of such) on the one hand and mere ideas on the other.
There is no such thing as a conceptual definition of this distinction (aside from circular definitions, i.e., of such as make a
hidden use of the object to be defined). Nor can it be maintained that at the base of this distinction there is a type of evidence, such as underlies, for example, the distinction between
red and blue. Yet, one needs this distinction in order to be able
to overcome solipsism. Solution: we shall make use of this
distinction unconcerned with the reproach that, in doing so, we
are guilty of the metaphysical "original sin." We regard the distinction as a category which we use in order that we might the
better find our way in the world of immediate sensations. The
"sense" and the justification of this distinction lies simply in
this achievement. But this is only a first step. We represent
the sense-impressions as conditioned by an "objective" and by
a "subjective" factor. For this conceptual distinction the/e also
is no logical-philosophical justification. But if we reject it, we
cannot escape solipsism. It is also the presupposition of every
kind of physical thinking. Here too, the only justification lies
in its usefulness. We are here concerned with "categories" or
schemes of thought, the selection of which is, in principle, entirely open to us and whose qualification can only be judged by
the degree to which its use contributes to making the totality
of the contents of consciousness "intelligible." The above
[p.674]
mentioned "objective factor" is the totality of such concepts
and conceptual relations as are thought of as independent of experience, viz., of perceptions. So long as we move within the
thus programmatically fixed sphere of thought we are thinking physically. Insofar as physical thinking justifies itself, in
the more than once indicated sense, by its ability to grasp experiences intellectually, we regard it as "knowledge of the
real."
After what has been said, the "real" in physics is to be
taken as a type of program, to which we are, however, not
forced to cling a priori. No one is likely to be inclined to attempt to give up this program within the realm of the "macroscopic" (location of the mark on the paperstrip "real"). But
the "macroscopic" and the "microscopic" are so inter-related
that it appears impracticable to give up this program in the
"microscopic" alone. Nor can I see any occasion anywhere
within the observable facts of the quantum-field for doing so,
unless, indeed, one clings a priori to the thesis that the description of nature by the statistical scheme of quantum-mechanics
is final.
The theoretical attitude here advocated is distinct from that
of Kant only by the fact that we do not conceive of the "categories" as unalterable (conditioned by the nature of the understanding) but as (in the logical sense) free conventions. They
appear to be a priori only insofar as thinking without the positing of categories and of concepts in general would be as impossible as is breathing in a vacuum.
From these meager remarks one will see that to me it must
seem a mistake to permit theoretical description to be directly
dependent upon acts of empirical assertions, as it seems to me
to be intended [for example] in Bohr's principle of complementarity, the sharp formulation of which, moreover, I have
been unable to achieve despite much effort which I have expended on it. From my point of view [such] statements or
measurements can occur only as special instances, viz., parts, of
physical description, to which I cannot ascribe any exceptional
position above the rest.
The above mentioned essays by Bohr and Pauli contain a
[p.675]
historical appreciation of my efforts in the area of physical statistics and quanta and, in addition, an accusation which is brought
forward in the friendliest of fashion. In briefest formulation
this latter runs as follows: "Rigid adherence to classical
theory." This accusation demands either a defense or the confession of guilt. The one or the other is, however, being rendered much more difficult because it is by no means immediately clear what is meant by "classical theory." Newton's theory
deserves the name of a classical theory. It has nevertheless been
abandoned since Maxwell and Hertz have shown that the
idea of forces at a distance has to be relinquished and that one
cannot manage without the idea of continuous "fields."
Eintein's goal is to explain everything in terms of a field theory.
The
opinion that continuous fields are to be viewed as the only acceptable basic concepts, which must also [be assumed to]
underlie the theory of the material particles, soon won out.
Now this conception became, so to speak, "classical;" but a
proper, and in principle complete, theory has not grown out of
it. Maxwell's theory of the electric field remained a torso, because it was unable to set up laws for the behavior of electric
density, without which there can, of course, be no such thing
as an electro-magnetic field. Analogously the general theory of
relativity furnished then a field theory of gravitation, but no
theory of the field-creating masses. (These remarks presuppose
it as self-evident that a field-theory may not contain any singularities, i.e., any positions or parts in space in which the field-
laws are not valid.)
Einstien's program is field theory.
Consequently there is, strictly speaking, today no such thing as
a classical field-theory; one can, therefore, also not rigidly adhere to it. Nevertheless, field-theory does exist as a program;
"Continuous functions in the four-dimensional [continuum]
as basic concepts of the theory. Rigid adherence to this program can rightfully be asserted of me. The deeper ground for
this lies in the following: The theory of gravitation showed
me that the non-linearity of these equations results in the fact
that this theory yields interactions among structures (localized
things) at all. But the theoretical search for non-linear equations is hopeless (because of too great variety of possibilities),
if one does not use the general principle of relativity (invariance
[p.676]
under general continuous co-ordinate-transformations).
In the meantime, however, it does not seem possible to formulate this principle, if one seeks to deviate from the above
program. Herein lies a coercion which I cannot evade. This for
my justification.
Nevertheless I am forced to weaken this justification by a
confession. If one disregards quantum structure, one can justify the introduction of the gik "operationally" by pointing to
the fact that one can hardly doubt the physical reality of the
elementary light cone which belongs to a point. In doing so one
implicitly makes use of the existence of an arbitrarily sharp
optical signal. Such a signal, however, as regards the quantum
facts, involves infinitely high frequencies and energies, and
therefore a complete destruction of the field to be determined.
That kind of a physical justification for the introduction of the
gik falls by the wayside, unless one limits himself to the
"macroscopic." The application of the formal basis of the
general theory of relativity to the "microscopic" can, therefore,
be based only upon the fact that that tensor is the formally
simplest covariant structure which can come under consideration. Such argumentation, however, carries no weight with anyone who doubts that we have to adhere to the continuum at
all. All honor to his doubt — but where else is there a passable
road?
Now I come to the theme of the relation of the theory of
relativity to philosophy. Here it is Reichenbach's piece of
work which, by the precision of deductions and by the sharpness
of his assertions, irresistibly invites a brief commentary. Robertson's lucid discussion also is interesting mainly from the standpoint of general epistemology, although it limits itself to the
narrower theme of "the theory of relativity and geometry."
To the question: Do you consider true what Reichenbach has
here asserted, I can answer only with Pilate's famous question:
"What is truth?"
Let us first take a good look at the question: Is a geometry
—looked at from the physical point of view—verifiable (viz.,
falsifiable) or not? Reichenbach, together with Helmholtz, says:
Yes, provided that the empirically given solid body realizes the
[p.677]
concept of "distance." Poincare says no and consequently is
condemned by Reichenbach. Now the following short conversation takes place:
Poincaré: The empirically given bodies are not rigid, and
consequently can not be used for the embodiment of geometric
intervals. Therefore, the theorems of geometry are not verifiable.
Reichenbach: I admit that there are no bodies which can
be immediately adduced for the "real definition" of the interval. Nevertheless, this real definition can be achieved by taking
the thermal volume-dependence, elasticity, electro- and
magneto-striction, etc., into consideration. That this is really
[and] without contradiction: possible, classical physics has surely
demonstrated.
Poincaré: In gaining the real definition improved by yourself you have made use of physical laws, the formulation of
which presupposes (in this case) Euclidean geometry. The
verification, of which you have spoken, refers, therefore, not
merely to geometry but to the entire system of physical laws
which constitute its foundation. An examination of geometry
by itself is consequently not thinkable. — Why should it consequently not be entirely up to me to choose geometry according to my own convenience (i.e., Euclidean) and to fit the remaining (in the usual sense "physical") laws to this choice in
such manner that there can arise no contradiction of the whole
with experience?
(The conversation cannot be continued in this fashion because
the respect of the [present] writer for Poincaré's superiority as
thinker and author does not permit it; in what follows therefore, an anonymous non-positivist is substituted for Poincaré.—)
Reichenbach: There is something quite attractive in this conception. But, on the other hand, it is noteworthy that the adherence to the objective meaning of length and to the interpretation of the differences of co-ordinates as distances (in pre-relativistic physics) has not led to complications. Should we not,
on the basis of this astounding fact, be justified in operating
further at least tentatively with the concept of the measurable
[p.678]
length, as if there were such things as rigid measuring-rods? In
any case it would have been impossible for Einstein de facto
(even if not theoretically) to set up the theory of general relativity, if he had not adhered to the objective meaning of length.
Against Poincaré's suggestion it is to be pointed out that
what really matters is not merely the greatest possible simplicity
of the geometry alone, but rather the greatest possible simplicity of all of physics (inclusive of geometry). This is what
is, in the first instance, involved in the fact that today we must
decline as unsuitable the suggestion to adhere to Euclidean
geometry.
Non-Positivist: If, under the stated circumstances, you hold
distance to be a legitimate concept, how then is it with your basic
principle (meaning = verifiability)? Do you not have to reach
the point where you must deny the meaning of geometrical
concepts and theorems and to acknowledge meaning only within the completely developed theory of relativity (which, however, does not yet exist at all as a finished product)? Do you
not have to admit that, in your sense of the word, no "meaning" can be attributed to the individual concepts and assertions
of a physical theory at all, and to the entire system only insofar
as it makes what is given in experience "intelligible?" Why do
the individual concepts which occur in a theory require any
specific justification anyway, if they are only indispensable
within the framework of the logical structure of the theory,
and the theory only in its entirety validates itself?
It seems to me, moreover, that you have not at all done
justice to the really significant philosophical achievement of
Kant. From Hume Kant had learned that there are concepts
(as, for example, that of causal connection), which play a
dominating role in our thinking, and which, nevertheless, can
not be deduced by means of a logical process from the empirically given (a fact which several empiricists recognize, it is
true, but seem always again to forget). What justifies the use
of such concepts? Suppose he had replied in this sense: Think-
ing is necessary in order to understand the empirically given,
and concepts and "categories" are necessary as indispensable
elements of thinking. If he had remained satisfied with this type
[p.679]
of an answer, he would have avoided scepticism and you would
not have been able to find fault with him. He, however, was
misled by the erroneous opinion — difficult to avoid in his time
— that Euclidean geometry is necessary to thinking and offers
assured (i.e., not dependent upon sensory experience) knowledge concerning the objects of "external" perception. From
this easily understandable error he concluded the existence of
synthetic judgments a priori, which are produced by the reason
alone, and which, consequently, can lay claim to absolute
validity. I think your censure is directed less against Kant himself than against those who today still adhere to the errors of "synthetic judgments a priori." —
I can hardly think of anything more stimulating as the basis
for discussion in an epistemological seminar than this brief
essay by Reichenbach (best taken together with Robertson's
essay).
What has been discussed thus far is closely related to
Bridgman's essay, so that it will be possible for me to express
myself quite briefly without having to harbor too much fear
that I shall be misunderstood. In order to be able to consider
a logical system as physical theory it is not necessary to demand
that all of its assertions can be independently interpreted and
"tested" "operationally}" de facto this has never yet been
achieved by any theory and can not at all be achieved. In order
to be able to consider a theory as a physical theory it is only
necessary that it implies empirically testable assertions in
general.
This formulation is insofar entirely unprecise as "testability"
is a quality which refers not merely to the assertion itself but
also to the co-ordination of concepts, contained in it, with experience. But it is probably hardly necessary for me to enter
upon a discussion of this ticklish problem, inasmuch as it is
not likely that there exist any essential differences of opinion at
this point. —
Margenau. This essay contains several original specific remarks, which I must consider separately:
To his Sec. 1: "Einstein's position . . . contains features
of rationalism and extreme empiricism. . . ." This remark Is
[p.680]
entirely correct. From whence comes this fluctuation? A logical
conceptual system is physics insofar as its concepts and assertions are necessarily brought into relationship with the world
of experiences. Whoever desires to set up such a system will
find a dangerous obstacle in arbitrary choice (embarras de
richesse). This is why he seeks to connect his concepts as directly
and necessarily as possible with the world of experience. In this
case his attitude is empirical. This path is often fruitful, but it
is always open to doubt, because the specific concept and the
individual assertion can, after all, assert something confronted
by the empirically given only in connection with the entire system. He then recognizes that there exists no logical path from
the empirically given to that conceptual world. His attitude becomes then more nearly rationalistic, because he recognizes the
logical independence of the system. The danger in this attitude
lies in the fact that in the search for the system one can lose
every contact with the world of experience. A wavering between these extremes appears to me unavoidable.
To his Sec. 2: I did not grow up in the Kantian tradition,
but came to understand the truly valuable which is to be found
in his doctrine, alongside of errors which today are quite obvious, only quite late. It is contained in the sentence: "The
real is not given to us, but put to us (aufgegeben) (by way
of a riddle)." This obviously means: There is such a thing as
a conceptual construction for the grasping of the inter-personal,
the authority of which lies purely in its validation. This conceptual construction refers precisely to the "real" (by definition), and every further question concerning the "nature of the
real" appears empty.
To his Sec. 4: This discussion has not convinced me at all.
For it is clear per se that every magnitude and every assertion
of a theory lays claim to "objective meaning" (within the
framework of the theory). A problem arises only when we
ascribe group-characteristics to a theory, i.e., if we assume or
postulate that the same physical situation admits of several
ways of description, each of which is to be viewed as equally
justified. For in this case we obviously cannot ascribe complete
objective meaning (for example the x-component of the
[p.681]
velocity of a particle or its x-co-ordinates) to the individual
(not eliminable) magnitudes. In this case, which has always
existed in physics, we have to limt ourselves to ascribing objective meaning to the general laws of the theory, i.e., we have
to demand that these laws are valid for every description of
the system which is recognized as justified by the group. It is,
therefore, not true that "objectivity" presupposes a group-
characteristic, but that the group-characteristic forces a refinement of the concept of objectivity. The positing of group characteristics is heuristically so important for theory, because this
characteristic always considerably limits the variety of the
mathematically meaningful laws.
Now there follows a claim that the group-characteristics
determine that the laws must have the form of differential
equations} I can not at all see this. Then Margenau insists that
the laws expressed by way of the differential equations (especially the partial ones) are "least specific." Upon what does
he base this contention? If they could be proved to be correct,
it is true that the attempt to ground physics upon differential
equations would then turn out to be hopeless. We are, however,
far from being able to judge whether differential laws of the
type to be considered have any solutions at all which are everywhere singularity-free; and, if so, whether there are too many
such solutions.
And now just a remark concerning the discussions about
the Einstein-Podolski-Rosen Paradox. I do not think that Margenau's defense of the "orthodox" ("orthodox" refers to the
thesis that the ψ-function characterizes the individual system
exhaustively) quantum position hits the essential [aspects].
Of the "orthodox" quantum theoreticians whose position I
know, Niels Bohr's seems to me to come nearest to doing justice
to the problem. Translated into my own way of putting it, he
argues as follows:
A two-particle ψ cannot be separated into the product of single-particle ψ's
If the partial systems A and B form a total system which is
described by its ψ-function ψ/(AB), there is no reason why
any mutually independent existence (state of reality) should be
ascribed to the partial systems A and B viewed separately, not
even if the partial systems are spatially separated from each
[p.682]
other at the particular time under consideration.
Einstein is troubled by the appearance of non-local behavior
The assertion
that, in this latter case, the real situation of B could not be
(directly) influenced by any measurement taken on A is, therefore, within the framework of quantum theory, unfounded and
(as the paradox shows) unacceptable.
By this way of looking at the matter it becomes evident that
the paradox forces us to relinquish one of the following two
assertions:
(i) the description by means of the ψ-function is complete (2) the real states of spatially separated objects are independent of each other.
If the separated systems are entangled, they cannot be independent
On the other hand, it is possible to adhere to (2), if one
regards the ψ-function as the description of a (statistical) ensemble of systems (and therefore relinquishes (1)). However,
this view blasts the framework of the "orthodox quantum
theory."
One more remark to Margenau's Sec. 7. In the characterization of quantum mechanics the brief little sentence will be
found: "on the classical level it corresponds to ordinary dynamics." This is entirely correct — cum grano salis; and it is
precisely this granum salis which is significant for the question
of interpretation.
If our concern is with macroscopic masses (billiard balls or
stars), we are operating with very short de Broglie-waves,
which are determinative for the behavior of the center of
gravity of such masses. This is the reason why it is possible to
arrange the quantum-theoretical description for a reasonable
time in such a manner that for the macroscopic way of viewing
things, it becomes sufficiently precise in position as well as in
momentum. It is true also that this sharpness remains for a
long time and that the quasi-points thus represented behave
just like the mass-points of classical mechanics. However, the
theory shows also that, after a sufficiently long time, the point-
like character of the ψ-function is completely lost to the center
of gravity-co-ordinates, so that one can no longer speak of any
quasi-localisation of the centers of gravity. The picture then
becomes, for example in the case of a single macro-mass-point,
quite similar to that involved in a single free electron.
[p.683]
If now, in accordance with the orthodox position, I view the
ψ-function as the complete description of a real matter of fact
for the individual case, I cannot but consider the essentially
unlimited lack of sharpness of the position of the (macroscopic)
body as real.
The idea that light falling on an object makes it more classical is assumed by the theory of decoherence
On the other hand, however, we know that, by
illuminating the body by means of a lantern at rest against the
system of co-ordinates, we get a (macroscopically judged)
sharp determination of position. In order to comprehend this I
must assume that that sharply defined position is determined
not merely by the real situation of the observed body, but also
by the act of illumination. This is again a paradox (similar to
the mark on the paperstrip in the above mentioned example).
The spook disappears only if one relinquishes the orthodox
standpoint, according to which the ψ-function is accepted as a
complete description of the single system.
It may appear as if all such considerations were just superfluous learned hairsplitting, which have nothing to do with
physics proper. However, it depends precisely upon such considerations in which direction one believes one must look for the
future conceptual basis of physics.
I close these expositions, which have grown rather lengthy,
concerning the interpretation of quantum theory with the reproduction of a brief conversation which I had with an important
theoretical physicist. He: "I am inclined to believe in telepathy." I: "This has probably more to do with physics than
with psychology." He: "Yes." —
The essays by Lenzen and Northrop both aim to treat my
occasional utterances of epistemological content systematically.
From those utterances Lenzen constructs a synoptic total picture, in which what is missing in the utterances is carefully and
with delicacy of feeling supplied. Everything said therein appears to me convincing and correct. Northrop uses these utterances as point of departure for a comparative critique of the
major epistemological systems. I see in this critique a masterpiece of unbiased thinking and concise discussion, which nowhere permits itself to be diverted from the essential.
The reciprocal relationship of epistemology and science is of
noteworthy kind. They are dependent upon each other. Epistemology
[p.684]
without contact with science becomes an empty
scheme. Science without epistemology is — insofar as it is think-
able at all — primitive and muddled. However, no sooner has
the epistemologist, who is seeking a clear system, fought his way
through to such a system, than he is inclined to interpret the
thought-content of science in the sense of his system and to
reject whatever does not fit into his system. The scientist, however, cannot afford to carry his striving for epistemological
systematic that far. He accepts gratefully the epistemological
conceptual analysis; but the external conditions, which are set
for him by the facts of experience, do not permit him to let
himself be too much restricted in the construction of his conceptual world by the adherence to an epistemological system.
He therefore must appear to the systematic epistemologist as
a type of unscrupulous opportunist: he appears as realist insofar
as he seeks to describe a world independent of the acts of
perception; as idealist insofar as he looks upon the concepts and
theories as the free inventions of the human spirit (not logically
derivable from what is empirically given); as positivist insofar
as he considers his concepts and theories justified only to the
extent to which they furnish a logical representation of relations
among sensory experiences. He may even appear as Platonist or
Pythagorean insofar as he considers the viewpoint of logical
simplicity as an indispensable and effective tool of his research.
All of this is splendidly elucidated in Lenzen's and North-
rop's essays.-----
And now a few remarks concerning the essays by E. A. Milne,
G. Lemaitre, and L. Infeld as concerns the cosmological problem:
Concerning Milne's ingenious reflections I can only say that
I find their theoretical basis too narrow. From my point of
view one cannot arrive, by way of theory, at any at least somewhat reliable results in the field of cosmology, if one makes
no use of the principle of general relativity.
As concerns Lemaitre's arguments in favor of the so-called
"cosmological constant" in the equations of gravitation, I must
admit that these arguments do not appear to me as sufficiently
convincing in view of the present state of our knowledge.
The introduction of such a constant implies a considerable
[p.685]
renunciation of the logical simplicity of theory, a renunciation
which appeared to me unavoidable only so long as one had no
reason to doubt the essentially static nature of space. After
Hubble's discovery of the "expansion" of the stellar system,
and since Friedmann's discovery that the unsupplemented equations involve the possibility of the existence of an average
(positive) density of matter in an expanding universe, the introduction of such a constant appears to me, from the theoretical
standpoint, at present unjustified.
The situation becomes complicated by the fact that the entire duration of the expansion of space to the present, based on
the equations in their simplest form, turns out smaller than
appears credible in view of the reliably known age of terrestrial
minerals. But the introduction of the "cosmological constant'"
offers absolutely no natural escape from the difficulty. This
latter difficulty is given by way of the numerical value of
Hubble's expansion-constant and the age-measurement of
minerals, completely independent of any cosmological theory,
provided that one interprets the Hubble-effect as Doppler-effect.
Everything finally depends upon the question: Can a spec-
tral line be considered as a measure of a "proper time" (EigenZeit) ds (ds2 = gik dxi dxk ), (if one takes into consideration
regions of cosmic dimensions)? Is there such a thing as a
natural object which incorporates the "natural-measuring-stick"
independently of its position in four-dimensional space? The
affirmation of this question made the invention of the general
theory of relativity psychologically possible) however this supposition is logically not necessary. For the construction of the
present theory of relativity the following is essential:
(1) Physical things are described by continuous functions, field-variables of four co-ordinates. As long as the topological connection is preserved, these latter can be freely chosen.[p.686] If (1) and (2) are accepted, (3) is plausible, but not necessary. The construction of mathematical theory rests exclusively upon (1) and (2). A complete theory of physics as a totality, in accordance with (1) and (2) does not yet exist. If it did exist, there would be no room for the supposition (3). For the objects used as tools for measurement do not lead an independent existence alongside of the objects implicated by the field-equations. - - It is not necessary that one should permit one's cosmological considerations to be restrained by such a sceptical attitude; but neither should one close one's mind towards them from the very beginning. - - - These reflections bring me to Karl Menger's essay. For the quantum-facts suggest the suspicion that doubt may also be raised concerning the ultimate usefulness of the program characterized in (1) and (2). There exists the possibility of doubting only (2) and, in doing so, to question the possibility of being able adequately to formulate the laws by means of differential equations, without dropping (1). The more radical effort of surrendering (1) with (2) appears to me — and I believe to Dr. Menger also — to lie more closely at hand. So long as no one has new concepts, which appear to have sufficient constructive power, mere doubt remains; this is, unfortunately, my own situation. Adhering to the continuum originates with me not in a prejudice, but arises out of the fact that I have been unable to think up anything organic to take its place. How is one to conserve four-dimensionality in essence (or in near approximation) and [at the same time] surrender the continuum? L. Infeld's essay is an independently understandable, excellent introduction into the so-called "cosmological problem" of the theory of relativity, which critically examines all essential points. - - - Max von Laue: An historical investigation of the development of the conservation postulates, which, in my opinion, is of lasting value. I think it would be worth while to make this essay easily accessible to students by way of independent publication. - - - [p.687] In spite of serious efforts I have not succeeded in quite understanding H. Dingle's essay, not even as concerns its aim. Is the idea of the special theory of relativity to be expanded in the sense that new group-characteristics, which are not implied by the Lorentz-invariance, are to be postulated? Are these postulates empirically founded or only by way of a trial "posited"? Upon what does the confidence in the existence of such group-characteristics rest? - - - Kurt Gödel's essay constitutes, in my opinion, an important contribution to the general theory of relativity, especially to the analysis of the concept of time. The problem here involved disturbed me already at the time of the building up of the general theory of relativity, without my having succeeded in clarifying it. Entirely aside from the relation of the theory of relativity to idealistic philosophy or to any philosophical formulation of questions, the problem presents itself as follows:
* * * * * *
I have the distressing feeling that I have expressed myself,
in this reply, not merely somewhat longwindedly but also
rather sharply. This observation may serve as my excuse: one
can really quarrel only with his brothers or close friends}
others are too alien [for that]. —
P.S. The preceding remarks refer to essays which were in
my hands at the end of January 1949. Inasmuch as the volume
was to have appeared in March, it was high time to write down
these reflections.
After they had been concluded I learned that the publication of the volume would experience a further delay and that
some additional important essays had come in. I decided,
nevertheless, not to expand my remarks further, which had already become too long, and to desist from taking any position
with reference to those essays which came into my hands after
the conclusion of my remarks.
Princeton, New Jersey February 1, 1949 For Teachers
For Scholars
|