Citation for this page in APA citation style.           Close


Philosophers

Mortimer Adler
Rogers Albritton
Alexander of Aphrodisias
Samuel Alexander
William Alston
Anaximander
G.E.M.Anscombe
Anselm
Louise Antony
Thomas Aquinas
Aristotle
David Armstrong
Harald Atmanspacher
Robert Audi
Augustine
J.L.Austin
A.J.Ayer
Alexander Bain
Mark Balaguer
Jeffrey Barrett
William Barrett
William Belsham
Henri Bergson
George Berkeley
Isaiah Berlin
Richard J. Bernstein
Bernard Berofsky
Robert Bishop
Max Black
Susanne Bobzien
Emil du Bois-Reymond
Hilary Bok
Laurence BonJour
George Boole
Émile Boutroux
Daniel Boyd
F.H.Bradley
C.D.Broad
Michael Burke
Lawrence Cahoone
C.A.Campbell
Joseph Keim Campbell
Rudolf Carnap
Carneades
Nancy Cartwright
Gregg Caruso
Ernst Cassirer
David Chalmers
Roderick Chisholm
Chrysippus
Cicero
Randolph Clarke
Samuel Clarke
Anthony Collins
Antonella Corradini
Diodorus Cronus
Jonathan Dancy
Donald Davidson
Mario De Caro
Democritus
Daniel Dennett
Jacques Derrida
René Descartes
Richard Double
Fred Dretske
John Dupré
John Earman
Laura Waddell Ekstrom
Epictetus
Epicurus
Austin Farrer
Herbert Feigl
Arthur Fine
John Martin Fischer
Frederic Fitch
Owen Flanagan
Luciano Floridi
Philippa Foot
Alfred Fouilleé
Harry Frankfurt
Richard L. Franklin
Bas van Fraassen
Michael Frede
Gottlob Frege
Peter Geach
Edmund Gettier
Carl Ginet
Alvin Goldman
Gorgias
Nicholas St. John Green
H.Paul Grice
Ian Hacking
Ishtiyaque Haji
Stuart Hampshire
W.F.R.Hardie
Sam Harris
William Hasker
R.M.Hare
Georg W.F. Hegel
Martin Heidegger
Heraclitus
R.E.Hobart
Thomas Hobbes
David Hodgson
Shadsworth Hodgson
Baron d'Holbach
Ted Honderich
Pamela Huby
David Hume
Ferenc Huoranszki
Frank Jackson
William James
Lord Kames
Robert Kane
Immanuel Kant
Tomis Kapitan
Walter Kaufmann
Jaegwon Kim
William King
Hilary Kornblith
Christine Korsgaard
Saul Kripke
Thomas Kuhn
Andrea Lavazza
Christoph Lehner
Keith Lehrer
Gottfried Leibniz
Jules Lequyer
Leucippus
Michael Levin
Joseph Levine
George Henry Lewes
C.I.Lewis
David Lewis
Peter Lipton
C. Lloyd Morgan
John Locke
Michael Lockwood
Arthur O. Lovejoy
E. Jonathan Lowe
John R. Lucas
Lucretius
Alasdair MacIntyre
Ruth Barcan Marcus
Tim Maudlin
James Martineau
Nicholas Maxwell
Storrs McCall
Hugh McCann
Colin McGinn
Michael McKenna
Brian McLaughlin
John McTaggart
Paul E. Meehl
Uwe Meixner
Alfred Mele
Trenton Merricks
John Stuart Mill
Dickinson Miller
G.E.Moore
Thomas Nagel
Otto Neurath
Friedrich Nietzsche
John Norton
P.H.Nowell-Smith
Robert Nozick
William of Ockham
Timothy O'Connor
Parmenides
David F. Pears
Charles Sanders Peirce
Derk Pereboom
Steven Pinker
Plato
Karl Popper
Porphyry
Huw Price
H.A.Prichard
Protagoras
Hilary Putnam
Willard van Orman Quine
Frank Ramsey
Ayn Rand
Michael Rea
Thomas Reid
Charles Renouvier
Nicholas Rescher
C.W.Rietdijk
Richard Rorty
Josiah Royce
Bertrand Russell
Paul Russell
Gilbert Ryle
Jean-Paul Sartre
Kenneth Sayre
T.M.Scanlon
Moritz Schlick
Arthur Schopenhauer
John Searle
Wilfrid Sellars
Alan Sidelle
Ted Sider
Henry Sidgwick
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong
J.J.C.Smart
Saul Smilansky
Michael Smith
Baruch Spinoza
L. Susan Stebbing
Isabelle Stengers
George F. Stout
Galen Strawson
Peter Strawson
Eleonore Stump
Francisco Suárez
Richard Taylor
Kevin Timpe
Mark Twain
Peter Unger
Peter van Inwagen
Manuel Vargas
John Venn
Kadri Vihvelin
Voltaire
G.H. von Wright
David Foster Wallace
R. Jay Wallace
W.G.Ward
Ted Warfield
Roy Weatherford
C.F. von Weizsäcker
William Whewell
Alfred North Whitehead
David Widerker
David Wiggins
Bernard Williams
Timothy Williamson
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Susan Wolf

Scientists

David Albert
Michael Arbib
Walter Baade
Bernard Baars
Jeffrey Bada
Leslie Ballentine
Marcello Barbieri
Gregory Bateson
Horace Barlow
John S. Bell
Mara Beller
Charles Bennett
Ludwig von Bertalanffy
Susan Blackmore
Margaret Boden
David Bohm
Niels Bohr
Ludwig Boltzmann
Emile Borel
Max Born
Satyendra Nath Bose
Walther Bothe
Jean Bricmont
Hans Briegel
Leon Brillouin
Stephen Brush
Henry Thomas Buckle
S. H. Burbury
Melvin Calvin
Donald Campbell
Sadi Carnot
Anthony Cashmore
Eric Chaisson
Gregory Chaitin
Jean-Pierre Changeux
Rudolf Clausius
Arthur Holly Compton
John Conway
Jerry Coyne
John Cramer
Francis Crick
E. P. Culverwell
Antonio Damasio
Olivier Darrigol
Charles Darwin
Richard Dawkins
Terrence Deacon
Lüder Deecke
Richard Dedekind
Louis de Broglie
Stanislas Dehaene
Max Delbrück
Abraham de Moivre
Bernard d'Espagnat
Paul Dirac
Hans Driesch
John Eccles
Arthur Stanley Eddington
Gerald Edelman
Paul Ehrenfest
Manfred Eigen
Albert Einstein
George F. R. Ellis
Hugh Everett, III
Franz Exner
Richard Feynman
R. A. Fisher
David Foster
Joseph Fourier
Philipp Frank
Steven Frautschi
Edward Fredkin
Benjamin Gal-Or
Howard Gardner
Lila Gatlin
Michael Gazzaniga
Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen
GianCarlo Ghirardi
J. Willard Gibbs
James J. Gibson
Nicolas Gisin
Paul Glimcher
Thomas Gold
A. O. Gomes
Brian Goodwin
Joshua Greene
Dirk ter Haar
Jacques Hadamard
Mark Hadley
Patrick Haggard
J. B. S. Haldane
Stuart Hameroff
Augustin Hamon
Sam Harris
Ralph Hartley
Hyman Hartman
Jeff Hawkins
John-Dylan Haynes
Donald Hebb
Martin Heisenberg
Werner Heisenberg
John Herschel
Basil Hiley
Art Hobson
Jesper Hoffmeyer
Don Howard
John H. Jackson
William Stanley Jevons
Roman Jakobson
E. T. Jaynes
Pascual Jordan
Eric Kandel
Ruth E. Kastner
Stuart Kauffman
Martin J. Klein
William R. Klemm
Christof Koch
Simon Kochen
Hans Kornhuber
Stephen Kosslyn
Daniel Koshland
Ladislav Kovàč
Leopold Kronecker
Rolf Landauer
Alfred Landé
Pierre-Simon Laplace
Karl Lashley
David Layzer
Joseph LeDoux
Gerald Lettvin
Gilbert Lewis
Benjamin Libet
David Lindley
Seth Lloyd
Hendrik Lorentz
Werner Loewenstein
Josef Loschmidt
Ernst Mach
Donald MacKay
Henry Margenau
Owen Maroney
David Marr
Humberto Maturana
James Clerk Maxwell
Ernst Mayr
John McCarthy
Warren McCulloch
N. David Mermin
George Miller
Stanley Miller
Ulrich Mohrhoff
Jacques Monod
Vernon Mountcastle
Emmy Noether
Donald Norman
Alexander Oparin
Abraham Pais
Howard Pattee
Wolfgang Pauli
Massimo Pauri
Wilder Penfield
Roger Penrose
Steven Pinker
Colin Pittendrigh
Walter Pitts
Max Planck
Susan Pockett
Henri Poincaré
Daniel Pollen
Ilya Prigogine
Hans Primas
Zenon Pylyshyn
Henry Quastler
Adolphe Quételet
Pasco Rakic
Nicolas Rashevsky
Lord Rayleigh
Frederick Reif
Jürgen Renn
Giacomo Rizzolati
Emil Roduner
Juan Roederer
Jerome Rothstein
David Ruelle
David Rumelhart
Tilman Sauer
Ferdinand de Saussure
Jürgen Schmidhuber
Erwin Schrödinger
Aaron Schurger
Sebastian Seung
Thomas Sebeok
Franco Selleri
Claude Shannon
Charles Sherrington
David Shiang
Abner Shimony
Herbert Simon
Dean Keith Simonton
Edmund Sinnott
B. F. Skinner
Lee Smolin
Ray Solomonoff
Roger Sperry
John Stachel
Henry Stapp
Tom Stonier
Antoine Suarez
Leo Szilard
Max Tegmark
Teilhard de Chardin
Libb Thims
William Thomson (Kelvin)
Richard Tolman
Giulio Tononi
Peter Tse
Alan Turing
Francisco Varela
Vlatko Vedral
Mikhail Volkenstein
Heinz von Foerster
Richard von Mises
John von Neumann
Jakob von Uexküll
C. S. Unnikrishnan
C. H. Waddington
John B. Watson
Daniel Wegner
Steven Weinberg
Paul A. Weiss
Herman Weyl
John Wheeler
Wilhelm Wien
Norbert Wiener
Eugene Wigner
E. O. Wilson
Günther Witzany
Stephen Wolfram
H. Dieter Zeh
Semir Zeki
Ernst Zermelo
Wojciech Zurek
Konrad Zuse
Fritz Zwicky

Presentations

Biosemiotics
Free Will
Mental Causation
James Symposium
 
P. H. Nowell-Smith

In his 1948 article in Mind, Freewill and Moral Responsibility, Nowell-Smith recaps the basic arguments of the determinist-compatibilist philosopher. Although there were ancient logical arguments for compatibilism, starting with Chrysippus, it is Thomas Hobbes and David Hume who put the arguments on a materialist physical basis.

Nowell-Smith cites R. E. Hobart, who had refined Hume's compatibilism in his landmark 1934 essay Free Will As Involving Determination And Inconceivable Without It.

Hobart correctly identified the need for some determination in the act of willing, without which there could not be moral responsibility. But Nowell-Smith demanded strict determinism.

Unlike Hobart, who admitted the possibility of some indeterminism and even absolute chance in the courses of action which "present themselves" to our will as alternative possibilities, Nowell-Smith makes the classic error of confusing indeterminism with total chance. He thinks that any real chance would render the world a complete chaos. He does not see that only adequate determinism is required.

Here is Nowell-Smith's concern about randomness (Mind, vol. 57, January, 1948)
The fallacy of [Incompatibilism] has often been exposed and the clearest proof that it is mistaken or at least muddled lies in showing that I could not be free to choose what I do unless determinism is correct. For the simplest actions could not be performed in an indeterministic universe. If I decide, say, to eat a piece of fish, I cannot do so if the fish is liable to turn into a stone or to disintegrate in mid-air or to behave in any other utterly unpredictable manner. (p.47)

Nowell-Smith's desire for a determined choice is satisfied by a two-stage model for free will, where the choice is adequately determined, even if the generation of alternative possibilities has involved indeterminism.

Six years later, Nowell-Smith again visited the problem (or as the determinists called it, the pseudo-problem) of free will in his essay in Mind, "Libertarians and Determinists." In it he says puzzlingly, "It is an old criticism of libertarianism that it makes out voluntary and deliberate actions to be 'chance events ', and libertarians are as anxious to deny this 'indeterminist' theory as they are to deny determinism." (p.329)

One of the puzzling features of the controversy is the fact that it is, on the whole, the libertarians who insist that there is such a thing as the Problem of free will, while the so-called determinists tend to call this problem a pseudo-problem. (They admit, of course, that there are plenty of problems in this obscure area.) This is puzzling because, in a way, there can be no such thing as the Problem for the libertarian. He thinks that it is obvious, that we have some sort of immediate insight into the fact that men are sometimes responsible for what they do and that they would not be responsible if they were not free in some 'contra-causal' sense; and if this is so, it is obvious that men are free in this sense and no problem arises. Nor does he even require to use this argument; for, he says, we have an immediate and indefeasible awareness of freedom. Yet the very fact that he insists on there being a problem here- would seem to show that there is something unsatisfactory about his immediate awareness. (p.318)

The immediate awareness of freedom. Could it be by introspection that we know of the existence, at the moment of choice, of open possibilities? Do we, as it were, see these possibilities? When we talk of 'possibilities' in connexion with natural phenomena, we always say something that could be expressed by the use of the modal word 'may'. We say "it may rain or it may not" ; to add "both possibilities exist" is to add a rhetorical flourish. In the case of human choice we say "I can (could) do this; but on the other hand I can (could) do that". In many cases it would be absurd, at a common sense level, to doubt that this is so or that the speaker knows it to be so; but philosophers are rightly puzzled by such platitudes and rightly ask "Just what is it that you know?" The philosopher's doubts are not allayed by the answer "What you know is that two genuinely open possibilities exist". Nor, if he is puzzled by the question "How do I know that I can do either this or that?", is he satisfied by the answer "You know this because you 'see' that both possibilities exist". Moreover, even it it were true that he knows that he could choose either this or that by some kind of introspection, it could not be true that part of what he so knows is "and no one could predict which I shall choose". That he could only know by testing people's powers of prediction. (And, of course, he knows both that he can choose and to what extent people can predict by experience; not by inspecting his experience at the moment of choice, but in the sort of way that he knows his own name or the way home.)

Exactly the same argument applies to the interpretation of the phrase 'I could have acted otherwise'. This is something which the plain man would certainly say of many of the things he does. And, contrary to the libertarian thesis, be would say this of actions that involve neither obligation nor an effort of will. No doubt there are many important differences between making an effort to do one's duty and choosing a peach; but at the common sense level none of the phrases that we use to indicate a free choice ('open possibilities', 'alternative courses', 'could have chosen otherwise') apply to the one rather than to the other. In the last resort it is not the libertarian's belief in freedom in moral contexts, but his denial of freedom in other contexts that is paradoxical. (p.324)

In the same way, when we ask whether someone can do or could have done something, we are asking whether he will or would have been successful if he tries or had tried to do it; and his trying to do it presupposes his wanting to do it. It is absurd to speak of success or failure or to ask whether any- thing prevents a man from doing something without presupposing a desire to do it on his part. And it is this presupposition that we are expressly excluding when we ask "Could he still do it, even if he did not want to?" This question makes sense if it is construed as being analogous to "Is it a conductor although it is not now conducting?" For example, I do not now want to multiply 567 by 479; I have no earthly reason for making the attempt; yet I have no doubt that I can do this, that is to say that if I had a reason for trying, I should try and succeed. But to interpret it to mean "Can I do it, even granted that I have no reason for trying? is to construe it as being analogous to " Would it still be a conductor if the conditions under which it actually carries a charge are not fulfilled?" (p.327)

Prima facie, then, statements containing ' can ' and ' could' are not reports of what occurs or does not occur at a particular moment; their modality in itself suggests this,' and the onus of proof is on those who would construe them differently in the special case of being able to choose the path of duty in the face of temptation. And even if it were true that, in this special case, the modal sentence was used to report an intro- spected datum, it would be difficult to see how 'no one could have predicted which I would choose' or 'I created a rupture in causal continuity' could be either a part of or entailed by what was reported. Moreover, if we do construe the modal sentence in this way, we ought, I think, to be more puzzled than we are by the fact that questions of responsibility, of the propriety or impropriety of blaming someone, turn on the truth or falsity of 'he could have acted otherwise'.

I should like to emphasize again the fact that I am not grinding any kind of behaviourist axe here. To say that ' I could have acted otherwise' is not a report of what one 'sees ' when he looks within is not to say that it is in all cases true that a spectator knows better than a man himself what he could or could not have done if he had tried. (p.328)

The Concept of Forces. So far I seem to have been defending a form of determinism; but this is not the case. I have simply refrained from raising the familiar objections to determinism, which are just as fatal. For the fact is that ' determined ' and 'contra-causal? have not been analysed and until their meanings are made clear, until we know to what we are committed when we say that choice is or is not contra-causal, the disputants must be fighting in the dark. There are at least three different bogeys that go under the name of 'determinism' and they must be kept distinct because each requires a different technique of exorcism.

(i) There is logical determinism or fatalism, according to which we cannot help doing what we do since things are what they are and our actions will be what they will be. I shall forbear to comment on this brand of determinism, since I doubt whether anyone is now seriously deceived by it.

(ii) There is the theory that we might call 'literal mechanical determinism'. Every human action, no matter what else it may be, is a complex but determinate movement of a determinate body. Suppose that this body were, quite literally, a complex machine? Suppose that we could predict its every movement in accordance with the laws of classical mechanics if only we knew enough about the particles concerned? This is the eighteenth-century bogey, and about it one can say little except that it might be true, that there is nothing in the present trend of natural science to warrant it (indeed it seems to presuppose a misunderstanding of explanation and prediction even within natural science) and that, if it were true, our talk about human conduct would be quite different from what it actually is.

(iii) There is also the obscure, elusive and much more important theory that desires (and other motives) are somehow like mechanical forces. The mechanical analogy is recognized as an analogy, but accepted without criticism as a good one. The idea seems to be that a man (or a 'self') is like a billiard- ball on which certain forces (his desires) act. The determinists say that all his actions are determined by the strength and direction of the forces, as movements are in classical mechanics, so that he 'must' do what he does in the same sense that a billiard ball 'must' move as it does.

Here Nowell-Smith describes Robert Kane's "Self-Forming Actions" exactly
The libertarian agrees that this is true in the case of most human actions but wants to make a special exception in the case of those situations that involve a conflict between desires and the sense of duty. The interplay of the forces, he says, is liable to be upset by the operations of a special sort of force, to which there is no analogue in mechanics, called "will-energy". Of this force little can be said except that we all feel it within us (and that is why little needs to be said), that we can use it or fail to use it, that it is unpredictable in its operations and that our status as free, responsible beings depends on its existence. Just why an observer is supposed to be able to discover the exact nature of the other forces but not of "will-energy" is not made clear; but this must be the case, since it is held that all actions other than those involving the sense of duty are, in principle, predictable in a para-mechanical way.
Nowell Smith articles
Freewill and Moral Responsibility
For Teachers
For Scholars

Chapter 1.4 - The Philosophy Chapter 1.6 - The Scientists
Home Part Two - Knowledge
Normal | Teacher | Scholar