Citation for this page in APA citation style.           Close


Philosophers

Mortimer Adler
Rogers Albritton
Alexander of Aphrodisias
Samuel Alexander
William Alston
Anaximander
G.E.M.Anscombe
Anselm
Louise Antony
Thomas Aquinas
Aristotle
David Armstrong
Harald Atmanspacher
Robert Audi
Augustine
J.L.Austin
A.J.Ayer
Alexander Bain
Mark Balaguer
Jeffrey Barrett
William Barrett
William Belsham
Henri Bergson
George Berkeley
Isaiah Berlin
Richard J. Bernstein
Bernard Berofsky
Robert Bishop
Max Black
Susanne Bobzien
Emil du Bois-Reymond
Hilary Bok
Laurence BonJour
George Boole
Émile Boutroux
Daniel Boyd
F.H.Bradley
C.D.Broad
Michael Burke
Lawrence Cahoone
C.A.Campbell
Joseph Keim Campbell
Rudolf Carnap
Carneades
Nancy Cartwright
Gregg Caruso
Ernst Cassirer
David Chalmers
Roderick Chisholm
Chrysippus
Cicero
Randolph Clarke
Samuel Clarke
Anthony Collins
Antonella Corradini
Diodorus Cronus
Jonathan Dancy
Donald Davidson
Mario De Caro
Democritus
Daniel Dennett
Jacques Derrida
René Descartes
Richard Double
Fred Dretske
John Dupré
John Earman
Laura Waddell Ekstrom
Epictetus
Epicurus
Austin Farrer
Herbert Feigl
Arthur Fine
John Martin Fischer
Frederic Fitch
Owen Flanagan
Luciano Floridi
Philippa Foot
Alfred Fouilleé
Harry Frankfurt
Richard L. Franklin
Bas van Fraassen
Michael Frede
Gottlob Frege
Peter Geach
Edmund Gettier
Carl Ginet
Alvin Goldman
Gorgias
Nicholas St. John Green
H.Paul Grice
Ian Hacking
Ishtiyaque Haji
Stuart Hampshire
W.F.R.Hardie
Sam Harris
William Hasker
R.M.Hare
Georg W.F. Hegel
Martin Heidegger
Heraclitus
R.E.Hobart
Thomas Hobbes
David Hodgson
Shadsworth Hodgson
Baron d'Holbach
Ted Honderich
Pamela Huby
David Hume
Ferenc Huoranszki
Frank Jackson
William James
Lord Kames
Robert Kane
Immanuel Kant
Tomis Kapitan
Walter Kaufmann
Jaegwon Kim
William King
Hilary Kornblith
Christine Korsgaard
Saul Kripke
Thomas Kuhn
Andrea Lavazza
Christoph Lehner
Keith Lehrer
Gottfried Leibniz
Jules Lequyer
Leucippus
Michael Levin
Joseph Levine
George Henry Lewes
C.I.Lewis
David Lewis
Peter Lipton
C. Lloyd Morgan
John Locke
Michael Lockwood
Arthur O. Lovejoy
E. Jonathan Lowe
John R. Lucas
Lucretius
Alasdair MacIntyre
Ruth Barcan Marcus
Tim Maudlin
James Martineau
Nicholas Maxwell
Storrs McCall
Hugh McCann
Colin McGinn
Michael McKenna
Brian McLaughlin
John McTaggart
Paul E. Meehl
Uwe Meixner
Alfred Mele
Trenton Merricks
John Stuart Mill
Dickinson Miller
G.E.Moore
Thomas Nagel
Otto Neurath
Friedrich Nietzsche
John Norton
P.H.Nowell-Smith
Robert Nozick
William of Ockham
Timothy O'Connor
Parmenides
David F. Pears
Charles Sanders Peirce
Derk Pereboom
Steven Pinker
Plato
Karl Popper
Porphyry
Huw Price
H.A.Prichard
Protagoras
Hilary Putnam
Willard van Orman Quine
Frank Ramsey
Ayn Rand
Michael Rea
Thomas Reid
Charles Renouvier
Nicholas Rescher
C.W.Rietdijk
Richard Rorty
Josiah Royce
Bertrand Russell
Paul Russell
Gilbert Ryle
Jean-Paul Sartre
Kenneth Sayre
T.M.Scanlon
Moritz Schlick
Arthur Schopenhauer
John Searle
Wilfrid Sellars
Alan Sidelle
Ted Sider
Henry Sidgwick
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong
J.J.C.Smart
Saul Smilansky
Michael Smith
Baruch Spinoza
L. Susan Stebbing
Isabelle Stengers
George F. Stout
Galen Strawson
Peter Strawson
Eleonore Stump
Francisco Suárez
Richard Taylor
Kevin Timpe
Mark Twain
Peter Unger
Peter van Inwagen
Manuel Vargas
John Venn
Kadri Vihvelin
Voltaire
G.H. von Wright
David Foster Wallace
R. Jay Wallace
W.G.Ward
Ted Warfield
Roy Weatherford
C.F. von Weizsäcker
William Whewell
Alfred North Whitehead
David Widerker
David Wiggins
Bernard Williams
Timothy Williamson
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Susan Wolf

Scientists

David Albert
Michael Arbib
Walter Baade
Bernard Baars
Jeffrey Bada
Leslie Ballentine
Marcello Barbieri
Gregory Bateson
Horace Barlow
John S. Bell
Mara Beller
Charles Bennett
Ludwig von Bertalanffy
Susan Blackmore
Margaret Boden
David Bohm
Niels Bohr
Ludwig Boltzmann
Emile Borel
Max Born
Satyendra Nath Bose
Walther Bothe
Jean Bricmont
Hans Briegel
Leon Brillouin
Stephen Brush
Henry Thomas Buckle
S. H. Burbury
Melvin Calvin
Donald Campbell
Sadi Carnot
Anthony Cashmore
Eric Chaisson
Gregory Chaitin
Jean-Pierre Changeux
Rudolf Clausius
Arthur Holly Compton
John Conway
Jerry Coyne
John Cramer
Francis Crick
E. P. Culverwell
Antonio Damasio
Olivier Darrigol
Charles Darwin
Richard Dawkins
Terrence Deacon
Lüder Deecke
Richard Dedekind
Louis de Broglie
Stanislas Dehaene
Max Delbrück
Abraham de Moivre
Bernard d'Espagnat
Paul Dirac
Hans Driesch
John Eccles
Arthur Stanley Eddington
Gerald Edelman
Paul Ehrenfest
Manfred Eigen
Albert Einstein
George F. R. Ellis
Hugh Everett, III
Franz Exner
Richard Feynman
R. A. Fisher
David Foster
Joseph Fourier
Philipp Frank
Steven Frautschi
Edward Fredkin
Benjamin Gal-Or
Howard Gardner
Lila Gatlin
Michael Gazzaniga
Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen
GianCarlo Ghirardi
J. Willard Gibbs
James J. Gibson
Nicolas Gisin
Paul Glimcher
Thomas Gold
A. O. Gomes
Brian Goodwin
Joshua Greene
Dirk ter Haar
Jacques Hadamard
Mark Hadley
Patrick Haggard
J. B. S. Haldane
Stuart Hameroff
Augustin Hamon
Sam Harris
Ralph Hartley
Hyman Hartman
Jeff Hawkins
John-Dylan Haynes
Donald Hebb
Martin Heisenberg
Werner Heisenberg
John Herschel
Basil Hiley
Art Hobson
Jesper Hoffmeyer
Don Howard
John H. Jackson
William Stanley Jevons
Roman Jakobson
E. T. Jaynes
Pascual Jordan
Eric Kandel
Ruth E. Kastner
Stuart Kauffman
Martin J. Klein
William R. Klemm
Christof Koch
Simon Kochen
Hans Kornhuber
Stephen Kosslyn
Daniel Koshland
Ladislav Kovàč
Leopold Kronecker
Rolf Landauer
Alfred Landé
Pierre-Simon Laplace
Karl Lashley
David Layzer
Joseph LeDoux
Gerald Lettvin
Gilbert Lewis
Benjamin Libet
David Lindley
Seth Lloyd
Hendrik Lorentz
Werner Loewenstein
Josef Loschmidt
Ernst Mach
Donald MacKay
Henry Margenau
Owen Maroney
David Marr
Humberto Maturana
James Clerk Maxwell
Ernst Mayr
John McCarthy
Warren McCulloch
N. David Mermin
George Miller
Stanley Miller
Ulrich Mohrhoff
Jacques Monod
Vernon Mountcastle
Emmy Noether
Donald Norman
Alexander Oparin
Abraham Pais
Howard Pattee
Wolfgang Pauli
Massimo Pauri
Wilder Penfield
Roger Penrose
Steven Pinker
Colin Pittendrigh
Walter Pitts
Max Planck
Susan Pockett
Henri Poincaré
Daniel Pollen
Ilya Prigogine
Hans Primas
Zenon Pylyshyn
Henry Quastler
Adolphe Quételet
Pasco Rakic
Nicolas Rashevsky
Lord Rayleigh
Frederick Reif
Jürgen Renn
Giacomo Rizzolati
Emil Roduner
Juan Roederer
Jerome Rothstein
David Ruelle
David Rumelhart
Tilman Sauer
Ferdinand de Saussure
Jürgen Schmidhuber
Erwin Schrödinger
Aaron Schurger
Sebastian Seung
Thomas Sebeok
Franco Selleri
Claude Shannon
Charles Sherrington
David Shiang
Abner Shimony
Herbert Simon
Dean Keith Simonton
Edmund Sinnott
B. F. Skinner
Lee Smolin
Ray Solomonoff
Roger Sperry
John Stachel
Henry Stapp
Tom Stonier
Antoine Suarez
Leo Szilard
Max Tegmark
Teilhard de Chardin
Libb Thims
William Thomson (Kelvin)
Richard Tolman
Giulio Tononi
Peter Tse
Alan Turing
Francisco Varela
Vlatko Vedral
Mikhail Volkenstein
Heinz von Foerster
Richard von Mises
John von Neumann
Jakob von Uexküll
C. S. Unnikrishnan
C. H. Waddington
John B. Watson
Daniel Wegner
Steven Weinberg
Paul A. Weiss
Herman Weyl
John Wheeler
Wilhelm Wien
Norbert Wiener
Eugene Wigner
E. O. Wilson
Günther Witzany
Stephen Wolfram
H. Dieter Zeh
Semir Zeki
Ernst Zermelo
Wojciech Zurek
Konrad Zuse
Fritz Zwicky

Presentations

Biosemiotics
Free Will
Mental Causation
James Symposium
 
The Strong Cosmological Principle, Indeterminacy, and the Direction of Time
Chapter VIII of The Nature of Time, ed. T. Gold, Cornell, 1967
Summary

It is generally agreed that irreversibility in macroscopic systems has its origin in the asymmetry of the initial or boundary conditions that are normally imposed on them. This asymmetry has a statistical character. The irreversibility of transport phenomena, for example, depends on the irrelevance of microscopic information about initial states. Thus, in heat conduction a knowledge of the initial temperature distribution suffices for a prediction of the temperature distribution at ail later times. But if microscopic information is unnecessary for the prediction of future macrostates, it must be necessary for the prediction of past macrostates. In this way the postulate of microscopic irrelevance singles out a direction in time.

The modern notion of entropy as a measure of uncertainty enables one to formulate the assumption of microscopic irrelevance in precise mathematical terms. The difficulty lies in understanding where the uncertainty about initial states comes from. That a detailed microscopic description of a physical system comes closer to reality than a statistical description seems almost self-evident. But it is hard to reconcile this intuition with the postulate of microscopic irrelevance. One might, perhaps, be tempted to regard irreversibility as being contingent on the macroscopic viewpoint. But the problem of accounting for the asymmetric character of macroscopic initial and boundary conditions would still remain.

I wish to suggest that a natural solution to the problem emerges from considerations of the space-time structure of the universe as a whole.

Such an approach may at first sight seem unnecessarily speculative. But the problem of understanding why certain kinds of boundary and initial conditions are appropriate in macroscopic physics is essentially one of understanding how macroscopic systems are related to the rest of the universe. Cosmology seems to offer a more adequate framework for a discussion of this question than macroscopic physics.

In the present context cosmology must be understood in a broader sense than the usual one, for it is essential to consider not only the large-scale structure of the universe but the local irregularities as well. The behavior of a universe without irregularities is completely reversible. Relativistic models that expand indefinitely from a state of maximum density may equally well be thought of as contracting from a state of infinite dispersion; oscillating models, of course, are invariant under time reversal. As for the steady-state universe, time reversal converts it into a contracting universe with continuous annihilation of matter a process that would seem to be as acceptable as continuous creation. If, then, irreversibility is a property of the universe as a whole, it must be intimately related to the existence of local irregularities. What considerations can we rely on for guidance in constructing a realistic nonuniform model of the universe?

It is often said that the universe is unique. As applied to the actual universe, this statement is a truism ; but as applied to the class of conceivable model universes, it has considerable heuristic value. Used in this way, it is not a new principle peculiar to cosmology but merely an application of the usual criterion of economy or simplicity ; it directs us toward the simplest cosmological postulates whose consequences are in accord with observation. Cosmology in the restricted sense is based on the postulate of spatial uniformity and isotropy the so-called cosmological principle. As applied to a universe with local irregularities, the cosmological principle states that neither the mean density field nor the mean velocity field at a given instant of cosmic time serves to define a preferred position or direction in space.

Evidence of the first mention of the Strong Cosmological Principle? No earlier refernces
The obvious generalization of this postulate is a statement that I shall call the strong cosmological principle: Every spatial section of the universe is statistically homogeneous and isotropic. By this I mean that any complete mathematical description of the universe is invariant under spatial translation and rotation, so that at any given instant of cosmic time there are no preferred positions or directions in space.

The mathematical properties of statistically homogeneous and isotropic distributions are familiar from the theory of turbulence. However, the strong cosmological principle has a basically different meaning from the assumption of statistical homogeneity and isotropy in turbulence theory.

When we describe the state of a bounded system in statistical terms, we ignore a large quantity of detailed information about the system, because it is inaccessible or uninteresting or both. Nevertheless, we regard the detailed information as meaningful and potentially relevant. We could, for example, make detailed predictions about a particular realization of a turbulent flow if we knew enough about the initial and boundary conditions. The situation is fundamentally different in an unbounded distribution characterized by statistical homogeneity and isotropy.

Let us first consider the case of an infinite universe satisfying the strong cosmological principle. It can be shown that a statistical description specifies the microscopic state of such a universe as closely as it can be specified. Conversely, the average properties of such a universe - "average" being used here to mean a spatial average - completely determine all the statistical quantities joint probability distributions, moments, and so on that figure in the statistical description. In short, an infinite, statistically homogeneous and isotropic universe contains no microscopic information.

As the simplest example of such a universe, consider a Poisson distribution of mass points in Euclidean space. This distribution is characterized by a single number, the mathematical expectation of the number density of points in a cell of arbitrary volume. Because the distribution is ergodic, this expectation can be approximated arbitrarily closely by a spatial average extended over a sufficiently large region of space. Now suppose that we try to compare two realizations of the same Poisson distribution. Let us focus attention on a particular finite volume in the first realization. Dividing this volume into cells, we may characterize the distribution of mass points within it by a set of occupation numbers. No matter how large the volume or how small the cells, the probability associated with this set of occupation numbers is, of course, finite. Hence it must be possible to find in the second realization a volume — in fact infinitely many volumes — in which the distribution of mass points reproduces the distribution in the first region to any given degree of precision. It follows that the two realizations are indistinguishable.

Essentially the same argument applies to any statistically homogeneous and isotropie distribution of infinite extent.

The argument applies also to finite, oscillating, model universes, provided that we regard the time axis as a closed loop. The statistical description specifies a complete ensemble of finite realizations, ail of which are on exactly the same footing.

If the preceding considerations are correct, the strong cosmological principle can account in a general way for the irrelevance of microscopic information in certain macroscopic contexts. But of course microscopic information is not always irrelevant. We are therefore obliged to consider how situations in which it is irrelevant actually arise. This leads directly to the problem of the formation of astronomical systems. Fortunately, we are here concerned only with a few broad aspects of this problem, which may be amenable to more or less rigorous investigation. Although such an investigation hàs been begun, it is still in a preliminary stage [Layzer, "A Preface to Cosmogony," Ap.J., 138, 174, 1963]. Nevertheless, a brief account of the fines along which it is proceeding may illuminate the present discussion.

Near the beginning of the expansion, when, as I shall assume, the density of matter was extremely high, the distribution of matter must have been much simpler than it is now. If we go sufficiently far back in time, we may even find that only a small number of free parameters or perhaps none at all is needed to specify the state of the universe completely. It is conceivable, for example, that the state of maximum compression is unique, being determined entirely by physical laws. Suppose that we take some sufficiently simple early state of the universe as our starting point. Can we then infer from the laws of physics how local irregularities will subsequently form and develop, and thereby predict the highly complex distribution of matter and motion we observe today? I have tried to show that the gradual development of local irregularities, leading ultimately to the formation of a hierarchy of self-gravitating systems, results from gravitational interactions in an expanding medium, after electromagnetic processes in an early stage of the expansion have caused the energy per unit mass associated with the local structure to assume its present (negative) value. For the purpose of the present discussion, then, let us assume that one can arrive at a statistical description of the present-day universe by tracing its development from an earlier state characterized by a small number of parameters. We have already concluded that the description, in spite of its statistical character, is complete. What implications does this picture of the universe and its evolution have for the nature of time?

Although our only assumption concerns the spatial structure of the inverse, our picture does exhibit a clear asymmetry between the two directions of time, because the spatial structure automatically causes the postulate of microscopic irrelevance to be satisfied. Since the universe is at the same time a single realization and a complete ensemble of realizations, its microscopic properties are entirely determined by statistical laws. It follows that a mathematical description of the universe can "unfold" in one direction only; by definition, this is the direction of the future. Thus the future is uniquely characterized by its predictability. On the other band, the present state contains traces of the past only, not of the future. Thus memory pertains uniquely to the past.

These features of the temporal structure of the universe have obvious correlates in our subjective experience of time. We remember the past but not the future; we can predict the future but not the past; without records, the historian's task would be impossible. Finally, the awareness of succession—the feeling of time gradually unfolding (though not always at the same rate)—corresponds to the way in which the mathematical description unfolds ; in the description, as in the reality, one must traverse the past in order to reach the future. In these matters, as with other aspects of perception and awareness, the structure of subjective experience seems to correspond in a more or less simple way to the structure of our mathematical description of what is being experienced.

REFERENCES

"A Preface to Cosmogony : I. The Energy Equation and the Virial Theorem for Cosmic Distributions," Ap. J., 138 (July, 1963), 174.
"The Formation of Stars and Galaxies: Unified Hypotheses," Annual Reviews of Astronomy and Astrophysics, 2 (1964).
"A Unified Approach to Cosmology," paper presented in the Summer Seminar on Relativity Theory and Astrophysics, sponsored by the American Mathematical Society, 1965.

COMMENTS (The attendees included Hermann Bondi, Richard Feynman, Thomas Gold, Martin Harwit, Roger Penrose, Philip Morrison, John Wheeler,

WHEELER

For the sake of clarity, I should say that the concept of a single quantum state of the universe is really rather different from the idea that there is a unique state of maximum condensation for an oscillating universe. The concept I was speaking about was one of an ergodic universe which undergoes a different kind of bounce each time. It bounces, so to speak, in accordance with a kind of probability factor governing the chances about how a cycle is related to the one preceding it. No other essential information is given. This is a very loose way of talking about something that should be treated as a quantum-mechanical system. I do not know how to improve on this treatment. I would not think of a unique state of maximum condensation, nor even of a unique macrostate.

MORRISON

Would you then in some sense envision that there is a predictability, in the sense of an expectation value of any operator, but not that the realization of any given development in a system should come from a single measurement?

WHEELER

I do not even know how to talk sensibly about this question because I do not know how to describe the measurement of this system. It has to be measured from the inside. One cannot form a wave pattern if he is talking about a system that is built out of one quantum state. This is a question for the "relative state formulation" type of description. There is a significant difference in interpretation.

HARWIT

The problem Layzer described looks very much like what Lifshitz did. He started out with a homogeneous, isotropic universe which is quite arbitrary, except that he set the cosmological constant equal to zero. Then, for all linear types of interaction, he traced the evolution of general, growing tensorial perturbations. Unless some nonlinearity is introduced which will complicate the theory, I do not see how this description would differ from the one you suggest in which the initial state is a superposition of different harmonics, which then evolve at calculable rates. What are the differences between your treatment and Lifshitz'?

LAYZER

Lifshitz studied the rate of growth of linear disturbances and showed that in fact some grew and others decayed, but that if one relied on statistical fluctuations to provide the initial irregularities, they would not grow large enough in the available time to account for the existence of _galaxies. My approach proceeds from a consideration of the energy associated with local irregularities and of the spectral distribution of :his energy. At present the local irregularities — chiefly galaxies and galaxy clusters have a mean binding energy per unit mass of about 1014 erg/gm. It can be shown that as we look backward in time this number will remain approximately constant as long as gravitational forces dominate the motions of particles. On the other hand, the amplitude of the density fluctuations will diminish as we look farther and farther back in time. Specifically, the binding energy per unit mass is proportional to the product α2Gρλ2, where α is the r.m.s. fractional density fluctuation, G is Newton's constant, ρ is the mean density, and λ is the density-autocorrelation distance. This formula, by the way, is not restricted to small values of α. As the universe expands, ρ varies as S-3 and increases no faster than S, where S is the cosmic scale factor. Hence α2 increases at least as fast as S. The upshot of this argument is that enough binding energy to account for the existence of galaxies and other astronomical systems can be stored in very inconspicuous density fluctuations at a sufficiently early stage iof the cosmic expansion.

But these initial density fluctuations, while inconspicuous, are nevertheless very much greater than the random fluctuations considered by Lifshitz. How do they arise? Again we may profitably consider the energetic aspects of the problem. I mentioned that the binding energy per unit mass was approximately conserved as long as gravitational forces dominated the motions of particles. At a sufficiently early stage in the cosmic expansion, when the mean density is comparable to atomic density, matter will be fully ionized and, if large-scale density fluctuations have not yet come into being, Coulomb forces will greatly overshadow the gravitational forces. You will recall that the electrostatic interaction between a proton and an electron is 1039 times as great as the gravitational interaction. In these circumstances it can be shown that the mean energy per unit mass associated with local irregularities is not conserved but decreases. Rough estimates indicate that Coulomb interactions at this stage of the expansion could produce a negative mean energy of the required magnitude, but more detailed calculations are needed to decide whether this will actually happen. Such calculations are now in progress. The temperature. is assumed to be zero initially, and the effects of nuclear reactions, Coulomb interactions, and radiation are all taken into account.

To sum up, Lifshitz' treatment and mine are mutually compatible, but they focus on different aspects of the problem. The apparent contradiction between Lifshitz' result and mine vanishes when one recognizes that the initial conditions contemplated in the two treatments are very different and that in my treatment nongravitational forces play an essential part in shaping the energy spectrum associated with local irregularities at an early stage of the cosmic expansion.

GOLD

Your question about information is the famous geneticist's problem. Either the information content required to construct a human is entirely in the genes, or else the information content of the genes is much less than the required amount. The question is essentially about how the information should be defined. It is not clear to me whether we should define the quantity of information in such a way that it appears to grow spontaneously, or whether we should define it so that the content of information is conserved.

MORRISON

That is exactly what I would have said. This question is the same as that of whether the number π contains infinite or a relatively small amount of information. I think that Layzer's view must be that it contains an infinite amount, and of course there is a certain plausibility to that. But this view also implies that the initial stage or quantum state of energy should be calculable without error. Any error would be enormously magnified. This question about information is the central issue.

BONDI

It seems to me that in any scientific work we must agree to disregard certain things. We must disregard certain features of experiments in order to undertake a formal treatment. If we had to give full details of any phenomenon in the classical picture, certainly we could never predict anything at all.

We can apply this principle of relevance to the significant subs stems of universe only if there is an infinity of them, either because universe is infinite in space or because it is infinite in time either through being in a steady state or being an oscillating universe. With a single circle of growth, we would be very much limited in applying this principle. I think this is the way to get around the problem of uniqueness. What I am saying probably is essentially equivalent to Layzer's point of view, but unless we make some such assumption about this, then we are caught in the uniqueness complex, which means essentially that things are unpredictable.

LAYZER

The behavior of the universe can be both unique and predictable if admit the kind of indeterminacy discussed in my paper — that is, regard a certain kind of microscopic information about the universe as unspecified beforehand. As far as I can see, this point of view does not bring us into conflict with experiment. We can, of course, acquire microscopic information of the kind I say is not specified beforehand, but we need to expend negative entropy to do it. That is, we must in a sense supply the required information ourselves. If we do not actually do this, then, I suggest, no significance can be attached to the statement that, say, a particular atom is at a particular place in space and time and not at some other place.

MORRISON

What do you mean by saying that ,no significance is ever attachéd to such a statement? Do you mean simply that some things cannot be predictable on this basis, and that these things are therefore irrelevant? If you give any independent criteria of significance, things might satisfy it, but it is only internali information that you set in advance.

LAYZER

By significant information I mean information that ought to figure in a complete description of the universe. Conversely, I would regard as insignificant any information whose existence had no observable consequences.

Normal | Teacher | Scholar